Christopher Janaway
- Published in print:
- 2007
- Published Online:
- September 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780199279692
- eISBN:
- 9780191707407
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199279692.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter argues that Nietzsche's conception of will to power underlies his explanations of moral values, and that its manifestations may be outward-directed or inward-directed, achieve genuine ...
More
This chapter argues that Nietzsche's conception of will to power underlies his explanations of moral values, and that its manifestations may be outward-directed or inward-directed, achieve genuine power or the feeling of power, and result in healthy or unhealthy states. In Genealogy II Nietzsche presents his historiographical principle concerning interpretation and origin, in which he implicates will to power: all interpretation is one thing exerting power over another, and Nietzsche blurs distinctions between natural and intentional explanation. The notion that the natural world is will to power is then discussed. Nietzsche does not propound a metaphysics of the world as thing in itself, but does explain all natural processes in terms of relations of dominance, in the human case the interaction of sub-personal drives or ‘under-wills’. Maudemarie Clark's reading of ‘the world as will to power’ as a projection of Nietzsche's values rather than a genuine assertion is examined and rejected.Less
This chapter argues that Nietzsche's conception of will to power underlies his explanations of moral values, and that its manifestations may be outward-directed or inward-directed, achieve genuine power or the feeling of power, and result in healthy or unhealthy states. In Genealogy II Nietzsche presents his historiographical principle concerning interpretation and origin, in which he implicates will to power: all interpretation is one thing exerting power over another, and Nietzsche blurs distinctions between natural and intentional explanation. The notion that the natural world is will to power is then discussed. Nietzsche does not propound a metaphysics of the world as thing in itself, but does explain all natural processes in terms of relations of dominance, in the human case the interaction of sub-personal drives or ‘under-wills’. Maudemarie Clark's reading of ‘the world as will to power’ as a projection of Nietzsche's values rather than a genuine assertion is examined and rejected.
John Richardson
- Published in print:
- 1996
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780195098464
- eISBN:
- 9780199833597
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195098463.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter develops the core idea that “the world is will to power” – what I call Nietzsche's “power ontology.” I give careful analyses of “will” and “power,” and clarify how he thinks these are ...
More
This chapter develops the core idea that “the world is will to power” – what I call Nietzsche's “power ontology.” I give careful analyses of “will” and “power,” and clarify how he thinks these are things’ essence or being. I distinguish between two basic forms that will to power can take – the active and the reactive – which will lie at the root of his values. The chapter then shows how this notion of will to power grounds Nietzsche's conception of persons as systems or syntheses of such wills (or drives), as well as his distinction of three basic types of persons – master, slave, and overman – each clarified as a specific way such a system of drives can be organized.Less
This chapter develops the core idea that “the world is will to power” – what I call Nietzsche's “power ontology.” I give careful analyses of “will” and “power,” and clarify how he thinks these are things’ essence or being. I distinguish between two basic forms that will to power can take – the active and the reactive – which will lie at the root of his values. The chapter then shows how this notion of will to power grounds Nietzsche's conception of persons as systems or syntheses of such wills (or drives), as well as his distinction of three basic types of persons – master, slave, and overman – each clarified as a specific way such a system of drives can be organized.
John Richardson
- Published in print:
- 1996
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780195098464
- eISBN:
- 9780199833597
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195098463.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
My overall project is to show that Nietzsche's ideas do cohere into a philosophical system comparable to his predecessors’ – despite his own strong attacks on the system, and on these predecessors. ...
More
My overall project is to show that Nietzsche's ideas do cohere into a philosophical system comparable to his predecessors’ – despite his own strong attacks on the system, and on these predecessors. This system centers around his view of the world as will to power. I work to make this notion conceptually precise, and to show how it extends into his wealth of other thoughts, including his analysis of the basic types of persons and societies, his insistence that the world is “not being but becoming,” his values of individuality and self‐creating, his attacks on morality, and his critique and affirmation of truth. The claim that Nietzsche promotes such a systematic view seems inconsistent with his well‐known “perspectivism”; I argue that the latter issues from his conception of these wills to power as perspectives, and that this source shows us both the forces and limits of that doctrine.Less
My overall project is to show that Nietzsche's ideas do cohere into a philosophical system comparable to his predecessors’ – despite his own strong attacks on the system, and on these predecessors. This system centers around his view of the world as will to power. I work to make this notion conceptually precise, and to show how it extends into his wealth of other thoughts, including his analysis of the basic types of persons and societies, his insistence that the world is “not being but becoming,” his values of individuality and self‐creating, his attacks on morality, and his critique and affirmation of truth. The claim that Nietzsche promotes such a systematic view seems inconsistent with his well‐known “perspectivism”; I argue that the latter issues from his conception of these wills to power as perspectives, and that this source shows us both the forces and limits of that doctrine.
James Davison Hunter
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- May 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199730803
- eISBN:
- 9780199777082
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199730803.003.0009
- Subject:
- Religion, Religion and Society
Power now does the work that culture used to do. This is seen in the tendency toward the politicization of nearly everything. Politicization is most visibly manifested in the role ideology has come ...
More
Power now does the work that culture used to do. This is seen in the tendency toward the politicization of nearly everything. Politicization is most visibly manifested in the role ideology has come to play in public life, the well-established predisposition to interpret all of public life through the filter of partisan beliefs, values, ideals, and attachments. As a consequence, we find it difficult to think in ways to address public problems or issues in any way that is not political. Politicization means that the final arbiter within most of social life is the coercive power of the state. Our times amply demonstrate that it is far easier to force one’s will upon others through legal and political means than it is to persuade them or negotiate compromise with them. What adds pathos to this situation is the presence of ressentiment, defined by a combination of anger, envy, hate, rage, and revenge.Less
Power now does the work that culture used to do. This is seen in the tendency toward the politicization of nearly everything. Politicization is most visibly manifested in the role ideology has come to play in public life, the well-established predisposition to interpret all of public life through the filter of partisan beliefs, values, ideals, and attachments. As a consequence, we find it difficult to think in ways to address public problems or issues in any way that is not political. Politicization means that the final arbiter within most of social life is the coercive power of the state. Our times amply demonstrate that it is far easier to force one’s will upon others through legal and political means than it is to persuade them or negotiate compromise with them. What adds pathos to this situation is the presence of ressentiment, defined by a combination of anger, envy, hate, rage, and revenge.
Krzysztof Michalski
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- October 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780691143460
- eISBN:
- 9781400840212
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691143460.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
This chapter examines what links the seemingly conflicting, or even mutually exclusive, concepts of eternity and passing, and Paradise and its loss. To life as a cup running over, to life as divinity ...
More
This chapter examines what links the seemingly conflicting, or even mutually exclusive, concepts of eternity and passing, and Paradise and its loss. To life as a cup running over, to life as divinity humanized, to human life marked by the effort to move out beyond everything human, to life flooded in a sunlight that is not human—to this irreducible aspect of human life Nietzsche applies the term overman, and the chapter once again returns to the character of Zarathustra in examining this concept. The chapter then turns to next concept that Nietzsche uses to characterize life—the will to power: “Where I found the living, there I found will to power.”Less
This chapter examines what links the seemingly conflicting, or even mutually exclusive, concepts of eternity and passing, and Paradise and its loss. To life as a cup running over, to life as divinity humanized, to human life marked by the effort to move out beyond everything human, to life flooded in a sunlight that is not human—to this irreducible aspect of human life Nietzsche applies the term overman, and the chapter once again returns to the character of Zarathustra in examining this concept. The chapter then turns to next concept that Nietzsche uses to characterize life—the will to power: “Where I found the living, there I found will to power.”
Peter Poellner
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198250630
- eISBN:
- 9780191598258
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198250630.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
In contrast with views that attribute the biological utility of beliefs to their truth, Nietzsche maintains that their relative utility renders them proportionately more likely to be idiosyncratic ...
More
In contrast with views that attribute the biological utility of beliefs to their truth, Nietzsche maintains that their relative utility renders them proportionately more likely to be idiosyncratic expressions of species‐relative concerns. Nietzsche's sceptical ‘argument from utility’—the inference from the practical utility of beliefs to the improbability of their being metaphysically true—is examined and rejected. It is argued that Nietzsche is an early proponent of naturalized epistemology. His objections to the ‘best explanation’ defence of metaphysical realism are discussed. It emerges that the ‘evolutionary’ strand of thought is incompatible with his other sceptical arguments. The chapter pursues Nietzsche's doctrine that the ‘ruling drives’ representing the dominant manifestation of the will to power in an individual determine the standards for validation, evidence, and truth. The discussion proceeds to an examination of Nietzsche's remarks that the external world is created in a manner depending on the specific form of the will to power instantiated by the empirical subject.Less
In contrast with views that attribute the biological utility of beliefs to their truth, Nietzsche maintains that their relative utility renders them proportionately more likely to be idiosyncratic expressions of species‐relative concerns. Nietzsche's sceptical ‘argument from utility’—the inference from the practical utility of beliefs to the improbability of their being metaphysically true—is examined and rejected. It is argued that Nietzsche is an early proponent of naturalized epistemology. His objections to the ‘best explanation’ defence of metaphysical realism are discussed. It emerges that the ‘evolutionary’ strand of thought is incompatible with his other sceptical arguments. The chapter pursues Nietzsche's doctrine that the ‘ruling drives’ representing the dominant manifestation of the will to power in an individual determine the standards for validation, evidence, and truth. The discussion proceeds to an examination of Nietzsche's remarks that the external world is created in a manner depending on the specific form of the will to power instantiated by the empirical subject.
Peter Poellner
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198250630
- eISBN:
- 9780191598258
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198250630.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
Examines Nietzsche's anti‐essentialism (the denial of metaphysical truth) in the context of the metaphysics of the will to power, which posits an ontology of interactive and causally efficacious ...
More
Examines Nietzsche's anti‐essentialism (the denial of metaphysical truth) in the context of the metaphysics of the will to power, which posits an ontology of interactive and causally efficacious quanta of force characterized exclusively by relational properties. It is argued that this ontological model is marred by a fundamental incoherence. The concluding remarks touch upon the problem of relativism of truth and self‐reference. An attempt is made to situate the metaphysics of the will in the context of Nietzsche's whole philosophy.Less
Examines Nietzsche's anti‐essentialism (the denial of metaphysical truth) in the context of the metaphysics of the will to power, which posits an ontology of interactive and causally efficacious quanta of force characterized exclusively by relational properties. It is argued that this ontological model is marred by a fundamental incoherence. The concluding remarks touch upon the problem of relativism of truth and self‐reference. An attempt is made to situate the metaphysics of the will in the context of Nietzsche's whole philosophy.
Christopher Janaway
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198250036
- eISBN:
- 9780191597817
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198250037.003.0014
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
Gives some of the background to the reception of Schopenhauer's philosophy by both Wittgenstein and Nietzsche, and then examines the influence on each of them of Schopenhauer's conceptions of self ...
More
Gives some of the background to the reception of Schopenhauer's philosophy by both Wittgenstein and Nietzsche, and then examines the influence on each of them of Schopenhauer's conceptions of self and will. In Wittgenstein's early notebooks and Tractatus, the notion of the subject's not being a part of the world and of happiness lying in not willing are distinctly Schopenhauerian notions. Wittgenstein's later pre‐occupation with the relation of willing and acting show a lasting influence from Schopenhauer. In Nietzsche's case, The Birth of Tragedy is transparently influenced by Schopenhauer's views on the thing in itself and individuation, while the later doctrine of will to power is designed as an alternative to Schopenhauer's will to life. Nietzsche's later philosophy makes continual reference to Schopenhauer even in its determination to oppose metaphysics and the unitary ‘I’.Less
Gives some of the background to the reception of Schopenhauer's philosophy by both Wittgenstein and Nietzsche, and then examines the influence on each of them of Schopenhauer's conceptions of self and will. In Wittgenstein's early notebooks and Tractatus, the notion of the subject's not being a part of the world and of happiness lying in not willing are distinctly Schopenhauerian notions. Wittgenstein's later pre‐occupation with the relation of willing and acting show a lasting influence from Schopenhauer. In Nietzsche's case, The Birth of Tragedy is transparently influenced by Schopenhauer's views on the thing in itself and individuation, while the later doctrine of will to power is designed as an alternative to Schopenhauer's will to life. Nietzsche's later philosophy makes continual reference to Schopenhauer even in its determination to oppose metaphysics and the unitary ‘I’.
Robin Small
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- July 2005
- ISBN:
- 9780199278077
- eISBN:
- 9780191602702
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199278075.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
Detailed discussion of Nietzsche’s later thought continues in a further chapter. His often-expressed hostility towards Darwinism is consistent with a preoccupation with themes that are central to the ...
More
Detailed discussion of Nietzsche’s later thought continues in a further chapter. His often-expressed hostility towards Darwinism is consistent with a preoccupation with themes that are central to the Darwinian tradition, such as the struggle for existence, adaptation, selection and ‘fitness’. Nietzsche’s idea of the ‘will to power’ signals a dramatic shift away from the hedonistic psychology he had championed throughout his partnership with Rée, and is also intended to provide the basis for a kind of natural selection, but one which is for individual exceptionality rather than for survival or reproduction.Less
Detailed discussion of Nietzsche’s later thought continues in a further chapter. His often-expressed hostility towards Darwinism is consistent with a preoccupation with themes that are central to the Darwinian tradition, such as the struggle for existence, adaptation, selection and ‘fitness’. Nietzsche’s idea of the ‘will to power’ signals a dramatic shift away from the hedonistic psychology he had championed throughout his partnership with Rée, and is also intended to provide the basis for a kind of natural selection, but one which is for individual exceptionality rather than for survival or reproduction.
Robert G. Morrison
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238652
- eISBN:
- 9780191679711
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238652.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion
Although Nietzsche's proposed answer to the prospect of nihilism — the creation of new values — was a task he did not complete, he did leave us with his monistic alternative and replacement for God, ...
More
Although Nietzsche's proposed answer to the prospect of nihilism — the creation of new values — was a task he did not complete, he did leave us with his monistic alternative and replacement for God, which would have functioned as the arbitrator in his proposed creation of new values — his vision of existence characterized as Wille zur Macht or ‘will to power’. It is only through this notion that one can make overall sense of Nietzsche. As a principle of explanation, it brings together and unites much that in isolation seems contradictory and even bizarre, and it is also the maxim which underpins his thinking on subjects such as culture, art, morality, philosophy, religion, as well as providing a continuity between his earlier and later writings, despite the fact that the will to power did not explicitly appear until Zarathustra. This chapter shows that it is an explanatory principle gleaned from Nietzsche's understanding of human nature and the natural sciences, and it provides a new and interesting perspective on human history and culture as well as providing the new Weltanschauung upon which the post-nihilistic future would be built.Less
Although Nietzsche's proposed answer to the prospect of nihilism — the creation of new values — was a task he did not complete, he did leave us with his monistic alternative and replacement for God, which would have functioned as the arbitrator in his proposed creation of new values — his vision of existence characterized as Wille zur Macht or ‘will to power’. It is only through this notion that one can make overall sense of Nietzsche. As a principle of explanation, it brings together and unites much that in isolation seems contradictory and even bizarre, and it is also the maxim which underpins his thinking on subjects such as culture, art, morality, philosophy, religion, as well as providing a continuity between his earlier and later writings, despite the fact that the will to power did not explicitly appear until Zarathustra. This chapter shows that it is an explanatory principle gleaned from Nietzsche's understanding of human nature and the natural sciences, and it provides a new and interesting perspective on human history and culture as well as providing the new Weltanschauung upon which the post-nihilistic future would be built.
Robert R. Williams
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- January 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199656059
- eISBN:
- 9780191744846
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199656059.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion
Chapter 3 explores Nietzsche’s concept of the contest. His early essay on Homer’s Contest shows that the contest is a social institution that restrains and limits violence, and thus is comparable to ...
More
Chapter 3 explores Nietzsche’s concept of the contest. His early essay on Homer’s Contest shows that the contest is a social institution that restrains and limits violence, and thus is comparable to Hegel’s account of the struggle for recognition that culminates mastery and servitude. The contest is oriented towards competition, but not in order to produce a winner and a loser, or victor and vanquished. The guiding idea is that no one should be the best. The idea is that contestation itself is intrinsically worthwhile because it drives the competitors to greater levels of excellence. This assumes that the other has an affirmative rather than a merely negative significance. The contest is a social institution, grounded in an intersubjectively constituted common will, even though it is justified principally by instrumental considerations about producing greater individual excellence. The chapter examines Lawrence Hatab’s claim that inherent in the contest is an agonistic view of the will to power itself, and the germ of a theory of affirmative, noble community, one that has potential convergences with Hegel’s concepts of recognition and ethical life.Less
Chapter 3 explores Nietzsche’s concept of the contest. His early essay on Homer’s Contest shows that the contest is a social institution that restrains and limits violence, and thus is comparable to Hegel’s account of the struggle for recognition that culminates mastery and servitude. The contest is oriented towards competition, but not in order to produce a winner and a loser, or victor and vanquished. The guiding idea is that no one should be the best. The idea is that contestation itself is intrinsically worthwhile because it drives the competitors to greater levels of excellence. This assumes that the other has an affirmative rather than a merely negative significance. The contest is a social institution, grounded in an intersubjectively constituted common will, even though it is justified principally by instrumental considerations about producing greater individual excellence. The chapter examines Lawrence Hatab’s claim that inherent in the contest is an agonistic view of the will to power itself, and the germ of a theory of affirmative, noble community, one that has potential convergences with Hegel’s concepts of recognition and ethical life.
Tsarina Doyle
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780748628070
- eISBN:
- 9780748652594
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Edinburgh University Press
- DOI:
- 10.3366/edinburgh/9780748628070.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter examines Friedrich Nietzsche's metaphysics by addressing his justification of the will to power. It shows that the attribution of a metaphysics to Nietzsche is both textually and ...
More
This chapter examines Friedrich Nietzsche's metaphysics by addressing his justification of the will to power. It shows that the attribution of a metaphysics to Nietzsche is both textually and philosophically defensible because the will to power derives from Nietzsche's perspectivism. It discusses Nietzsche's argument that the will to power is a comprehensive perspective that unifies opposing points of view rather than reducing all explanation to one of them.Less
This chapter examines Friedrich Nietzsche's metaphysics by addressing his justification of the will to power. It shows that the attribution of a metaphysics to Nietzsche is both textually and philosophically defensible because the will to power derives from Nietzsche's perspectivism. It discusses Nietzsche's argument that the will to power is a comprehensive perspective that unifies opposing points of view rather than reducing all explanation to one of them.
Robert Pippin
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- September 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199231560
- eISBN:
- 9780191716119
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199231560.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
Although there are several recognizable themes in Nietzsche's discussion of freedom (such as independence from societal pressures and some sort of self-rule or individual sovereignty), at many places ...
More
Although there are several recognizable themes in Nietzsche's discussion of freedom (such as independence from societal pressures and some sort of self-rule or individual sovereignty), at many places he seems especially interested in the issue of ‘self-overcoming’. In these passages he considers freedom a kind of perpetual self-overcoming. Freedom is not a metaphysical capacity to have done otherwise, nor the unconstrained expression of one's identity, but: (i) a psychological self-relation, a relation to one's own drives, desires, commitments, etc; (ii) a difficult achievement that depends neither on force of will or self-knowledge, or reflective endorsement alone; (iii) a paradoxical form of mindedness, at once affirmative and negative, whole-hearted and ironic (a ‘tension of the spirit’); and (iv) a form of self-mastery or an expression of the ‘will to power’, very unlike what traditional interpretations ascribe to Nietzsche. This chapter argues against literary self-creation models of this self-relation, and focuses attention on the underlying issue in all the relevant passages: the proper status of Nietzschean ‘psychology’, and why Nietzsche considers such a psychology the new ‘queen of the sciences’.Less
Although there are several recognizable themes in Nietzsche's discussion of freedom (such as independence from societal pressures and some sort of self-rule or individual sovereignty), at many places he seems especially interested in the issue of ‘self-overcoming’. In these passages he considers freedom a kind of perpetual self-overcoming. Freedom is not a metaphysical capacity to have done otherwise, nor the unconstrained expression of one's identity, but: (i) a psychological self-relation, a relation to one's own drives, desires, commitments, etc; (ii) a difficult achievement that depends neither on force of will or self-knowledge, or reflective endorsement alone; (iii) a paradoxical form of mindedness, at once affirmative and negative, whole-hearted and ironic (a ‘tension of the spirit’); and (iv) a form of self-mastery or an expression of the ‘will to power’, very unlike what traditional interpretations ascribe to Nietzsche. This chapter argues against literary self-creation models of this self-relation, and focuses attention on the underlying issue in all the relevant passages: the proper status of Nietzschean ‘psychology’, and why Nietzsche considers such a psychology the new ‘queen of the sciences’.
Robert C. Solomon
- Published in print:
- 2004
- Published Online:
- January 2005
- ISBN:
- 9780195160147
- eISBN:
- 9780199835065
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195160142.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
Nietzsche is obviously a very passionate philosopher. He also has a good deal to say about the passions. In particular, he distinguished between two sorts of passions, life-enhancing and ...
More
Nietzsche is obviously a very passionate philosopher. He also has a good deal to say about the passions. In particular, he distinguished between two sorts of passions, life-enhancing and life-stultifying. For good reason, he was cited by Freud and Adler as the progenitor of “Depth Psychology.” I explore Nietzsche views on emotions and offer a defense of the passions. I suggest that Nietzsche anticipates not only Freud but contemporary physiological theories of emotion. I also discuss Nietzsche’s conception of the “Will to Power” suggesting that the idea is both exaggerated in Nietzsche interpretation and disastrous in terms of Nietzsche’s own aims. I do defend a version of the will to power as the passionate life.Less
Nietzsche is obviously a very passionate philosopher. He also has a good deal to say about the passions. In particular, he distinguished between two sorts of passions, life-enhancing and life-stultifying. For good reason, he was cited by Freud and Adler as the progenitor of “Depth Psychology.” I explore Nietzsche views on emotions and offer a defense of the passions. I suggest that Nietzsche anticipates not only Freud but contemporary physiological theories of emotion. I also discuss Nietzsche’s conception of the “Will to Power” suggesting that the idea is both exaggerated in Nietzsche interpretation and disastrous in terms of Nietzsche’s own aims. I do defend a version of the will to power as the passionate life.
Robert G. Morrison
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238652
- eISBN:
- 9780191679711
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238652.003.0010
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion
In the Will to Power, Nietzsche envisages the cosmos as ‘a monster of energy, without beginning, without end,…a creating and destroying play of forces,…an eternal becoming that must return ...
More
In the Will to Power, Nietzsche envisages the cosmos as ‘a monster of energy, without beginning, without end,…a creating and destroying play of forces,…an eternal becoming that must return eternally’. This is Nietzsche's ‘Dionysian world’, the world as ‘will to power’. Within this world, man is a particular and discrete embodiment of this will to power, a particular configuration of a ‘play of forces’ emerging at a distinct point in the evolution of the natural world. Man is therefore a product of a world that precedes him. Buddhism, on the other hand, has never had a philosophy of nature, nor has it felt it necessary to have any definite view on the ultimate origins of man or the cosmos. As Nietzsche's notion of will to power has its paradigm in Hesiod's notion of Eris or Strife, this chapter uses the notion of Erōs as found in Plato's Symposium as a paradigm for tanhā.Less
In the Will to Power, Nietzsche envisages the cosmos as ‘a monster of energy, without beginning, without end,…a creating and destroying play of forces,…an eternal becoming that must return eternally’. This is Nietzsche's ‘Dionysian world’, the world as ‘will to power’. Within this world, man is a particular and discrete embodiment of this will to power, a particular configuration of a ‘play of forces’ emerging at a distinct point in the evolution of the natural world. Man is therefore a product of a world that precedes him. Buddhism, on the other hand, has never had a philosophy of nature, nor has it felt it necessary to have any definite view on the ultimate origins of man or the cosmos. As Nietzsche's notion of will to power has its paradigm in Hesiod's notion of Eris or Strife, this chapter uses the notion of Erōs as found in Plato's Symposium as a paradigm for tanhā.
Paul Katsafanas
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- May 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199645077
- eISBN:
- 9780191751912
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199645077.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter uses a roughly Nietzschean account of agency to argue that action has a second constitutive aim: power. It begins by offering a novel interpretation of Nietzsche’s obscure claim that all ...
More
This chapter uses a roughly Nietzschean account of agency to argue that action has a second constitutive aim: power. It begins by offering a novel interpretation of Nietzsche’s obscure claim that all actions manifest, and are to be evaluated in terms of, “will to power.” In particular, it argues that Nietzsche’s will to power thesis can be read as a version of constitutivism. This Nietzschean version of constitutivism is based on a series of subtle claims about the psychology of willing and the nature of satisfaction, which jointly imply that all actions aim at encountering and overcoming resistance (this is what Nietzsche means by “will to power”). After arguing that we should accept the Nietzschean points about willing and satisfaction, the chapter concludes that action constitutively aims at power.Less
This chapter uses a roughly Nietzschean account of agency to argue that action has a second constitutive aim: power. It begins by offering a novel interpretation of Nietzsche’s obscure claim that all actions manifest, and are to be evaluated in terms of, “will to power.” In particular, it argues that Nietzsche’s will to power thesis can be read as a version of constitutivism. This Nietzschean version of constitutivism is based on a series of subtle claims about the psychology of willing and the nature of satisfaction, which jointly imply that all actions aim at encountering and overcoming resistance (this is what Nietzsche means by “will to power”). After arguing that we should accept the Nietzschean points about willing and satisfaction, the chapter concludes that action constitutively aims at power.
Jeremy Fortier
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- September 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780226679396
- eISBN:
- 9780226679426
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226679426.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
In Thus Spoke Zarathustra Nietzsche uses the title character as a medium for exploring the project of a cultural founder or creator. Zarathustra’s project fundamentally differs from that of Free ...
More
In Thus Spoke Zarathustra Nietzsche uses the title character as a medium for exploring the project of a cultural founder or creator. Zarathustra’s project fundamentally differs from that of Free Spirits, since the Free Spirit project is in the first place one of self-cultivation, whereas Zarathustra’s project is (or begins as) one of cultivating broader human community. The motivating force that draws Zarathustra into engagement with the broad swath of humanity is his defining trait of love. Zarathustra’s love is not a romantic love that finds satisfaction in a particular person, but it is a kind of neediness which requires others for its fulfillment (others whom it can benefit through its creative activity). The drama of the work consists of Zarathustra’s attempt to fulfill this need (or determine whether it can be fulfilled). Zarathustra's self-understanding therefore evolves over the course of his journey, as he is forced to wrestle the question of how (or whether) his need for love can be made compatible with truth. On this reading, the primary function of the work's famous doctrines of the will to power and the eternal return is to drive forward Zarathustra's drama of evolving self-understanding.Less
In Thus Spoke Zarathustra Nietzsche uses the title character as a medium for exploring the project of a cultural founder or creator. Zarathustra’s project fundamentally differs from that of Free Spirits, since the Free Spirit project is in the first place one of self-cultivation, whereas Zarathustra’s project is (or begins as) one of cultivating broader human community. The motivating force that draws Zarathustra into engagement with the broad swath of humanity is his defining trait of love. Zarathustra’s love is not a romantic love that finds satisfaction in a particular person, but it is a kind of neediness which requires others for its fulfillment (others whom it can benefit through its creative activity). The drama of the work consists of Zarathustra’s attempt to fulfill this need (or determine whether it can be fulfilled). Zarathustra's self-understanding therefore evolves over the course of his journey, as he is forced to wrestle the question of how (or whether) his need for love can be made compatible with truth. On this reading, the primary function of the work's famous doctrines of the will to power and the eternal return is to drive forward Zarathustra's drama of evolving self-understanding.
Jean-Luc Marion
- Published in print:
- 2021
- Published Online:
- January 2022
- ISBN:
- 9780226684611
- eISBN:
- 9780226691398
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226691398.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion
Are Christians the most useful citizens in French society, precisely because they live as if already belonging to another world? Their utility is seen in relation to the dangers of the present ...
More
Are Christians the most useful citizens in French society, precisely because they live as if already belonging to another world? Their utility is seen in relation to the dangers of the present moment, characterized by nihilism. In nihilism, following Nietzsche, values possess no value in themselves, but are dependent on evaluation. Evaluation today is exchange-based, and thus unstable. “Values” has been produced and mastered by someone who decides them. This deciding involves the will willing its own elevation to power: the will to power. The answer to nihilism lies not in ceasing to will, but in willing differently. As the Gospels show, Jesus willed otherwise, willing the will of the Father. This different willing is the Christian path out of nihilism. By willing as Jesus willed, Christians begin to achieve the common good in its fullness as good of the communion, a nonpolitical model of political community. This communion is lived according to the counter logic to economic exchange found in the non-reciprocity of the gift. Christians, beneficiaries and actors of the gift, offer society a new agent of democracy, who precedes the economic proprietor of the self, acting with authority rather than power.Less
Are Christians the most useful citizens in French society, precisely because they live as if already belonging to another world? Their utility is seen in relation to the dangers of the present moment, characterized by nihilism. In nihilism, following Nietzsche, values possess no value in themselves, but are dependent on evaluation. Evaluation today is exchange-based, and thus unstable. “Values” has been produced and mastered by someone who decides them. This deciding involves the will willing its own elevation to power: the will to power. The answer to nihilism lies not in ceasing to will, but in willing differently. As the Gospels show, Jesus willed otherwise, willing the will of the Father. This different willing is the Christian path out of nihilism. By willing as Jesus willed, Christians begin to achieve the common good in its fullness as good of the communion, a nonpolitical model of political community. This communion is lived according to the counter logic to economic exchange found in the non-reciprocity of the gift. Christians, beneficiaries and actors of the gift, offer society a new agent of democracy, who precedes the economic proprietor of the self, acting with authority rather than power.
Christine Daigle
- Published in print:
- 2021
- Published Online:
- May 2022
- ISBN:
- 9781474487849
- eISBN:
- 9781399509626
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Edinburgh University Press
- DOI:
- 10.3366/edinburgh/9781474487849.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
This chapter further unpacks Nietzsche’s phenomenological view of consciousness as multi-layered and embodied. It delineates the topology of consciousness that emerges in key passages of Thus Spoke ...
More
This chapter further unpacks Nietzsche’s phenomenological view of consciousness as multi-layered and embodied. It delineates the topology of consciousness that emerges in key passages of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, such as “On the Despisers of the Body”, wherein his view of the body as “grand reason” emerges. It is important to understand how he repositions the ego, and thereby repositions agency and the traditional cogito as a tool for the conscious body. This understanding leads to an exploration of the key Nietzschean concept of perspectivism which is revisited as yet another phenomenological feature of Nietzsche’s thought. The chapter also discusses the notion of the soul as subjective multiplicity as it is presented in the first book of Beyond Good and Evil. This text is importantly connected to the topology of consciousness presented in Thus Spoke Zarathustra and to the notion of perspectivism. The soul, as multiple, is a dynamic becoming within which drives and affects compete in their interaction with the world, leading to the adoption of multiple perspectives. The chapter concludes by revisiting one of the most important passages in Nietzsche’s work with regards to the notion of will to power, aphorism 36 of Beyond Good and Evil. The analysis shows that this section serves to summarize Nietzsche’s views on intentional consciousness and its constitution of itself and the world.Less
This chapter further unpacks Nietzsche’s phenomenological view of consciousness as multi-layered and embodied. It delineates the topology of consciousness that emerges in key passages of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, such as “On the Despisers of the Body”, wherein his view of the body as “grand reason” emerges. It is important to understand how he repositions the ego, and thereby repositions agency and the traditional cogito as a tool for the conscious body. This understanding leads to an exploration of the key Nietzschean concept of perspectivism which is revisited as yet another phenomenological feature of Nietzsche’s thought. The chapter also discusses the notion of the soul as subjective multiplicity as it is presented in the first book of Beyond Good and Evil. This text is importantly connected to the topology of consciousness presented in Thus Spoke Zarathustra and to the notion of perspectivism. The soul, as multiple, is a dynamic becoming within which drives and affects compete in their interaction with the world, leading to the adoption of multiple perspectives. The chapter concludes by revisiting one of the most important passages in Nietzsche’s work with regards to the notion of will to power, aphorism 36 of Beyond Good and Evil. The analysis shows that this section serves to summarize Nietzsche’s views on intentional consciousness and its constitution of itself and the world.
Robert G. Morrison
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238652
- eISBN:
- 9780191679711
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238652.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion
This chapter presents an overview of Part II of this volume. One common and general feature shared by both Nietzsche and Buddhism is the centrality of man in a godless cosmos, in the sense that both ...
More
This chapter presents an overview of Part II of this volume. One common and general feature shared by both Nietzsche and Buddhism is the centrality of man in a godless cosmos, in the sense that both look to man, and not any external power, being, or numinous source, for their respective solutions to what they perceive as the problem(s) of existence. Another feature shared by both, and which is the main theme of Part II, is that their respective goals are to be achieved through a process of ‘self-overcoming’ (Selbstüberwindung in Nietzsche's case, citta-bhāvanā in Buddhism's), and this self-overcoming is understood as the spiritual expression of a more basic and natural force (will to power in Nietzsche's case, taᓧhāā in Buddhism's).Less
This chapter presents an overview of Part II of this volume. One common and general feature shared by both Nietzsche and Buddhism is the centrality of man in a godless cosmos, in the sense that both look to man, and not any external power, being, or numinous source, for their respective solutions to what they perceive as the problem(s) of existence. Another feature shared by both, and which is the main theme of Part II, is that their respective goals are to be achieved through a process of ‘self-overcoming’ (Selbstüberwindung in Nietzsche's case, citta-bhāvanā in Buddhism's), and this self-overcoming is understood as the spiritual expression of a more basic and natural force (will to power in Nietzsche's case, taᓧhāā in Buddhism's).