Michael Potter
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- January 2009
- ISBN:
- 9780199215836
- eISBN:
- 9780191721243
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199215836.003.0018
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
From a single proposition p we form its negation not-p. From two propositions p and q we form various further propositions, e.g., p or q, p and q, etc.; similarly (though less often) with three or ...
More
From a single proposition p we form its negation not-p. From two propositions p and q we form various further propositions, e.g., p or q, p and q, etc.; similarly (though less often) with three or more propositions. For each such method of forming propositions it is common to speak of a certain truth-function as corresponding to it. On the one hand, there is a function which takes senses of propositions as inputs and returns the sense of a proposition as output. On the other hand, there is a truth-function, i.e., a function taking some finite number of truth-values as arguments and giving a single truth-value as value, which is representable by a truth-table or truth-diagram. This chapter discusses the relationship between the two.Less
From a single proposition p we form its negation not-p. From two propositions p and q we form various further propositions, e.g., p or q, p and q, etc.; similarly (though less often) with three or more propositions. For each such method of forming propositions it is common to speak of a certain truth-function as corresponding to it. On the one hand, there is a function which takes senses of propositions as inputs and returns the sense of a proposition as output. On the other hand, there is a truth-function, i.e., a function taking some finite number of truth-values as arguments and giving a single truth-value as value, which is representable by a truth-table or truth-diagram. This chapter discusses the relationship between the two.
Denis McManus
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- January 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780199288021
- eISBN:
- 9780191713446
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199288021.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter explores Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘the general form of the proposition’ and argues that these too are informed by his desire to show that the impression that there are substantial ...
More
This chapter explores Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘the general form of the proposition’ and argues that these too are informed by his desire to show that the impression that there are substantial ‘logical truths’ is an illusion. It explores Wittgenstein’s understanding of logical inference as ‘unpacking’, his analysis of truth-functional connectives using truth-tables, his account of logical propositions as tautologies and contradictions, and the philosophical significance for Wittgenstein of providing a ‘topic-neutral’ account of logical inference and the logical connectives. Drawing on retrospective remarks of Wittgenstein’s, an explanation is offered on how he could have failed to recognize that his notion of the general form of the proposition is laden with problematic metaphysical commitments.Less
This chapter explores Wittgenstein’s remarks on ‘the general form of the proposition’ and argues that these too are informed by his desire to show that the impression that there are substantial ‘logical truths’ is an illusion. It explores Wittgenstein’s understanding of logical inference as ‘unpacking’, his analysis of truth-functional connectives using truth-tables, his account of logical propositions as tautologies and contradictions, and the philosophical significance for Wittgenstein of providing a ‘topic-neutral’ account of logical inference and the logical connectives. Drawing on retrospective remarks of Wittgenstein’s, an explanation is offered on how he could have failed to recognize that his notion of the general form of the proposition is laden with problematic metaphysical commitments.
Peter Hylton
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- May 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199286355
- eISBN:
- 9780191713309
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199286355.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
This chapter takes up an important and disputed issue in the interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, and uses ideas articulated in the previous chapter to shed light on it. ...
More
This chapter takes up an important and disputed issue in the interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, and uses ideas articulated in the previous chapter to shed light on it. Truth-functions are central to Wittgenstein's thought; they play the crucial role not only in accounting for logic but also in explaining the possibility of any language or thought beyond the most elementary. Yet his account of the truth functions is by no means easy to understand. In particular, Wittgenstein calls them operations, and insists that they must be sharply distinguished from functions; yet most of what he says about them seems to apply equally to functions. When Wittgenstein uses the word ‘function’ he is following Russell, and speaking of Russellian propositional functions. Reading him in this way can make sense of the contrasts he draws between functions and operations. This enables us to achieve a better understanding of his notion of an operation. On the basis of this understanding, it is argued that operations in his sense cannot be identified with ordinary mathematical functions or with Fregean functions. The account that Wittgenstein gives of them cannot be separated from his general project of reconceiving the way in which language and thought represent the world; we cannot understand it in other terms.Less
This chapter takes up an important and disputed issue in the interpretation of Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, and uses ideas articulated in the previous chapter to shed light on it. Truth-functions are central to Wittgenstein's thought; they play the crucial role not only in accounting for logic but also in explaining the possibility of any language or thought beyond the most elementary. Yet his account of the truth functions is by no means easy to understand. In particular, Wittgenstein calls them operations, and insists that they must be sharply distinguished from functions; yet most of what he says about them seems to apply equally to functions. When Wittgenstein uses the word ‘function’ he is following Russell, and speaking of Russellian propositional functions. Reading him in this way can make sense of the contrasts he draws between functions and operations. This enables us to achieve a better understanding of his notion of an operation. On the basis of this understanding, it is argued that operations in his sense cannot be identified with ordinary mathematical functions or with Fregean functions. The account that Wittgenstein gives of them cannot be separated from his general project of reconceiving the way in which language and thought represent the world; we cannot understand it in other terms.
Thomas Ricketts
- Published in print:
- 2002
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780195133264
- eISBN:
- 9780199833580
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195133269.003.0010
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
The paper examines Wittgenstein's criticisms of Frege's and Russell's views of logical segmentation encapsulated at Tractatus 4.431 and 4.063. These criticisms proceed from Wittgenstein's 1913 ...
More
The paper examines Wittgenstein's criticisms of Frege's and Russell's views of logical segmentation encapsulated at Tractatus 4.431 and 4.063. These criticisms proceed from Wittgenstein's 1913 conception of atomic sentences as models of reality and the distinctive conception of sense embedded in this conception. While Russell mistakenly assimilates the structure of truth‐functionally compound sentences to that of atomic sentences, Frege mistakenly makes the converse assimilation.Less
The paper examines Wittgenstein's criticisms of Frege's and Russell's views of logical segmentation encapsulated at Tractatus 4.431 and 4.063. These criticisms proceed from Wittgenstein's 1913 conception of atomic sentences as models of reality and the distinctive conception of sense embedded in this conception. While Russell mistakenly assimilates the structure of truth‐functionally compound sentences to that of atomic sentences, Frege mistakenly makes the converse assimilation.
Michael Potter
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- January 2009
- ISBN:
- 9780199215836
- eISBN:
- 9780191721243
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199215836.003.0021
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
The discussion of Wittgenstein's account of quantification in Chapter 20 left unaddressed what sort of theory of types it commits us to. To answer this question we need to look in more detail at the ...
More
The discussion of Wittgenstein's account of quantification in Chapter 20 left unaddressed what sort of theory of types it commits us to. To answer this question we need to look in more detail at the motivation for believing in logical types at all. That motivation derives from Russell's paradox, the problem which had originally attracted Wittgenstein's notice back in 1909. This chapter discusses Russell's theory of types, Wittgenstein's vicious circle principle, types as classes of propositions, types and molecular propositions, types and generality, uniting generality and truth-functions, the general form of proposition, and unsayability.Less
The discussion of Wittgenstein's account of quantification in Chapter 20 left unaddressed what sort of theory of types it commits us to. To answer this question we need to look in more detail at the motivation for believing in logical types at all. That motivation derives from Russell's paradox, the problem which had originally attracted Wittgenstein's notice back in 1909. This chapter discusses Russell's theory of types, Wittgenstein's vicious circle principle, types as classes of propositions, types and molecular propositions, types and generality, uniting generality and truth-functions, the general form of proposition, and unsayability.
Mathieu Marion
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- September 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199550470
- eISBN:
- 9780191701559
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199550470.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
The notion of operation plays a pivotal role in the symbolism of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: on the one hand, truth-functions are based on truth-operations; on the other, numbers are ...
More
The notion of operation plays a pivotal role in the symbolism of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: on the one hand, truth-functions are based on truth-operations; on the other, numbers are exponents of an operation. Considering that operations seem to be so central, it is amazing to notice how little is understood of Ludwig Wittgenstein's remarks: not enough attention has been paid in the past to the curious piece of symbolism of 6.01. What Wittgenstein says about the notion of operation very much resembles informal explanations of the notion of operator. Two differences with the set-theoretic notion of function were mentioned in Chapter 1: firstly, an operator is defined by describing how it transforms an input without defining the set of inputs, that is without defining its domain. Secondly, there is no restriction on the domain of some operators.Less
The notion of operation plays a pivotal role in the symbolism of the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: on the one hand, truth-functions are based on truth-operations; on the other, numbers are exponents of an operation. Considering that operations seem to be so central, it is amazing to notice how little is understood of Ludwig Wittgenstein's remarks: not enough attention has been paid in the past to the curious piece of symbolism of 6.01. What Wittgenstein says about the notion of operation very much resembles informal explanations of the notion of operator. Two differences with the set-theoretic notion of function were mentioned in Chapter 1: firstly, an operator is defined by describing how it transforms an input without defining the set of inputs, that is without defining its domain. Secondly, there is no restriction on the domain of some operators.
Stephen Neale
- Published in print:
- 2001
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780199247158
- eISBN:
- 9780191598081
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199247153.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Language
Introduces the criticisms put forward by philosophers such as Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty to the idea that one thing might represent another: that thoughts, utterances, and inscriptions are ...
More
Introduces the criticisms put forward by philosophers such as Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty to the idea that one thing might represent another: that thoughts, utterances, and inscriptions are said to have content by virtue of their power to represent reality; and that those that do the job accurately are true, they correspond to the facts, or mirror reality—they are representations of reality. The author then outlines the deductive proof that he will present in the book to show that Davidson's and Rorty's criticisms are unfounded. The content of the proof is based on the work of Kurt Gödel and W. V. Quine, and demonstrates conclusively that (i) any supposedly non‐truth‐functional operation must satisfy an exacting logical condition in order to avoid collapsing into a truth‐function, and (ii) any theory of facts, states of affairs, situations, or propositions must satisfy a corresponding condition if such entities are not to collapse into a unity. The three main sections of the chapter: examine the case against representations made by Davidson and Rorty, including Davidson's notorious argument against facts; discuss Rorty's critique of representational philosophy (his anti‐representationalism); and consider collapsing (or slingshot) arguments that discredit the existence of facts (and are used in the critique of the fact–representation distinction), as put forward by Gottlob Frege, and developed by Alonzo Church, Quine, Davidson, and Gödel. The last section of the chapter outlines the structure of the book.Less
Introduces the criticisms put forward by philosophers such as Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty to the idea that one thing might represent another: that thoughts, utterances, and inscriptions are said to have content by virtue of their power to represent reality; and that those that do the job accurately are true, they correspond to the facts, or mirror reality—they are representations of reality. The author then outlines the deductive proof that he will present in the book to show that Davidson's and Rorty's criticisms are unfounded. The content of the proof is based on the work of Kurt Gödel and W. V. Quine, and demonstrates conclusively that (i) any supposedly non‐truth‐functional operation must satisfy an exacting logical condition in order to avoid collapsing into a truth‐function, and (ii) any theory of facts, states of affairs, situations, or propositions must satisfy a corresponding condition if such entities are not to collapse into a unity. The three main sections of the chapter: examine the case against representations made by Davidson and Rorty, including Davidson's notorious argument against facts; discuss Rorty's critique of representational philosophy (his anti‐representationalism); and consider collapsing (or slingshot) arguments that discredit the existence of facts (and are used in the critique of the fact–representation distinction), as put forward by Gottlob Frege, and developed by Alonzo Church, Quine, Davidson, and Gödel. The last section of the chapter outlines the structure of the book.
P. F. Strawson
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198250159
- eISBN:
- 9780191598470
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198250150.003.0010
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
The view that the ordinary conditional ‘if p then q’ has the same meaning as the material conditional of standard truth‐functional logic confronts the more intuitive view that it imports, as part of ...
More
The view that the ordinary conditional ‘if p then q’ has the same meaning as the material conditional of standard truth‐functional logic confronts the more intuitive view that it imports, as part of its meaning, some ground‐consequent relation between antecedent and consequent clauses. Grice's powerful defence of the former position demonstrates that the operation of certain effective general principles of assertive discourse would normally ensure that the truth‐functional conditional carried a non‐conventional consequentialist implication. A defence of the contrary view rests on the fact that ‘p, so q’, which incontestably carries a consequentialist implication as part of its meaning, differs from ‘if p then q’ only in that the former conjoins asserted, the latter unasserted, propositions. There is plenty of occasion for the use of both ‘so’ and ‘if’. The balance of argument favours the consequentialist position.Less
The view that the ordinary conditional ‘if p then q’ has the same meaning as the material conditional of standard truth‐functional logic confronts the more intuitive view that it imports, as part of its meaning, some ground‐consequent relation between antecedent and consequent clauses. Grice's powerful defence of the former position demonstrates that the operation of certain effective general principles of assertive discourse would normally ensure that the truth‐functional conditional carried a non‐conventional consequentialist implication. A defence of the contrary view rests on the fact that ‘p, so q’, which incontestably carries a consequentialist implication as part of its meaning, differs from ‘if p then q’ only in that the former conjoins asserted, the latter unasserted, propositions. There is plenty of occasion for the use of both ‘so’ and ‘if’. The balance of argument favours the consequentialist position.
José L. Zalabardo
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- August 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780198743941
- eISBN:
- 9780191803949
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198743941.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter argues that Wittgenstein’s account of how we know that a proposition is a logical consequence of other propositions provides the main motivation for his flagship doctrine that every ...
More
This chapter argues that Wittgenstein’s account of how we know that a proposition is a logical consequence of other propositions provides the main motivation for his flagship doctrine that every proposition is a truth function of elementary propositions, as well as for his extraordinary demands on the propositions that serve as elementary—that they are independent of one another and that their constituents refer to simple items. It then considers the metaphysical and epistemological questions raised by the kind of analysis that, according to Wittgenstein, must be possible, concentrating on the relationship between logical structure and use. The chapter ends by considering the task of extending to non-elementary propositions the pictorial account of how propositions represent.Less
This chapter argues that Wittgenstein’s account of how we know that a proposition is a logical consequence of other propositions provides the main motivation for his flagship doctrine that every proposition is a truth function of elementary propositions, as well as for his extraordinary demands on the propositions that serve as elementary—that they are independent of one another and that their constituents refer to simple items. It then considers the metaphysical and epistemological questions raised by the kind of analysis that, according to Wittgenstein, must be possible, concentrating on the relationship between logical structure and use. The chapter ends by considering the task of extending to non-elementary propositions the pictorial account of how propositions represent.
Raymond S. Nickerson
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- November 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780190202996
- eISBN:
- 9780190249137
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190202996.003.0004
- Subject:
- Psychology, Cognitive Psychology
This chapter discusses truth functions and the concept of the material conditional. It introduces the criteria of assertability or acceptability; notes alogical aspects of conditionals as they are ...
More
This chapter discusses truth functions and the concept of the material conditional. It introduces the criteria of assertability or acceptability; notes alogical aspects of conditionals as they are used in everyday discourse; and distinguishes among truth, validity, and soundness in the context of argument evaluation.Less
This chapter discusses truth functions and the concept of the material conditional. It introduces the criteria of assertability or acceptability; notes alogical aspects of conditionals as they are used in everyday discourse; and distinguishes among truth, validity, and soundness in the context of argument evaluation.
José L. Zalabardo
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- August 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780198743941
- eISBN:
- 9780191803949
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198743941.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
The book puts forward an interpretation of some central ideas of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus concerning the structure of reality and our representations of it in thought and ...
More
The book puts forward an interpretation of some central ideas of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus concerning the structure of reality and our representations of it in thought and language. It presents the origins of Wittgenstein’s picture theory of propositional representation in Russell’s theories of judgment, arguing that the picture theory is Wittgenstein’s solution to some problems that he found in Russell’s position. It defends the view that, for Wittgenstein, facts in general, and the facts that play the role of propositions in particular, are not composite items, arising from the combination of their constituents. They are ultimate, irreducible units, and what we think of as their constituents are features that facts have in common with one another. These common features have built into them their possibilities of combination with other features into possible situations. This is presented as the source of the Tractarian account of non-actual possibilities. It is also the source of the idea that it is not possible to produce propositions answering to certain descriptions, including those that would give rise to Russell’s paradox. The book then considers Wittgenstein’s view that every proposition is a truth function of elementary propositions. It argues that this view is motivated by Wittgenstein’s epistemology of logic, according to which we should be able to see logical relations by inspecting the structures of propositions. Finally it considers the problems that we face if we try to extend the application of the picture theory from elementary propositions to truth functions of these.Less
The book puts forward an interpretation of some central ideas of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus concerning the structure of reality and our representations of it in thought and language. It presents the origins of Wittgenstein’s picture theory of propositional representation in Russell’s theories of judgment, arguing that the picture theory is Wittgenstein’s solution to some problems that he found in Russell’s position. It defends the view that, for Wittgenstein, facts in general, and the facts that play the role of propositions in particular, are not composite items, arising from the combination of their constituents. They are ultimate, irreducible units, and what we think of as their constituents are features that facts have in common with one another. These common features have built into them their possibilities of combination with other features into possible situations. This is presented as the source of the Tractarian account of non-actual possibilities. It is also the source of the idea that it is not possible to produce propositions answering to certain descriptions, including those that would give rise to Russell’s paradox. The book then considers Wittgenstein’s view that every proposition is a truth function of elementary propositions. It argues that this view is motivated by Wittgenstein’s epistemology of logic, according to which we should be able to see logical relations by inspecting the structures of propositions. Finally it considers the problems that we face if we try to extend the application of the picture theory from elementary propositions to truth functions of these.
Frederick C. Beiser
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- January 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199682959
- eISBN:
- 9780191763090
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682959.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
Chapter 3 is a discussion of Lotze’s early metaphysics and logic. One section is devoted to Lotze’s 1841 Metaphysik, an innovative text in the criticism of the metaphysical tradition and Hegelianism. ...
More
Chapter 3 is a discussion of Lotze’s early metaphysics and logic. One section is devoted to Lotze’s 1841 Metaphysik, an innovative text in the criticism of the metaphysical tradition and Hegelianism. Another section deals with Lotze’s early philosophy of physiology or the life sciences, especially his influential critique of the concept of Lebenskraft and his attempt to reconcile mechanical and teleological explanation. Still another section deals with Lotze’s 1843 Logik, attempting to specify how this text anticipates later developments in logic.Less
Chapter 3 is a discussion of Lotze’s early metaphysics and logic. One section is devoted to Lotze’s 1841 Metaphysik, an innovative text in the criticism of the metaphysical tradition and Hegelianism. Another section deals with Lotze’s early philosophy of physiology or the life sciences, especially his influential critique of the concept of Lebenskraft and his attempt to reconcile mechanical and teleological explanation. Still another section deals with Lotze’s 1843 Logik, attempting to specify how this text anticipates later developments in logic.