Mei Xu
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- February 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199233854
- eISBN:
- 9780191715532
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199233854.003.0004
- Subject:
- Mathematics, Applied Mathematics
This chapter presents a review of concurrent multiscale methods for coupling continuum, molecular, and quantum mechanics with a particular emphasis on the Bridging Domain Method. An expanded taxonomy ...
More
This chapter presents a review of concurrent multiscale methods for coupling continuum, molecular, and quantum mechanics with a particular emphasis on the Bridging Domain Method. An expanded taxonomy of multiscale methods is presented which highlights the role and characteristics of concurrent multiscale methods. Several popular 0 K methods are summarized: master-slave coupling, ONIOM, the Bridging Domain Method, the Bridging Scale Method and the Quasicontinuum method. The topic of ghost forces in the Bridging Domain Method is studied and the stability properties of Lagrange multiplier coupling methods are reviewed. Several methods for coupling molecular dynamics with continua are described: master-slave and handshake methods, the Bridging Domain Method, and the Bridging Scale Method. The conservation properties of the Bridging Domain Method are demonstrated. Numerical examples are presented which focus on the reduction of spurious phonon reflections from the continuum/molecular interfaces in the Bridging Domain Method. Examples of the simulation of cracks and defects in graphene using a modified ONIOM method to couple continuum, molecular, and quantum subdomain are also given.Less
This chapter presents a review of concurrent multiscale methods for coupling continuum, molecular, and quantum mechanics with a particular emphasis on the Bridging Domain Method. An expanded taxonomy of multiscale methods is presented which highlights the role and characteristics of concurrent multiscale methods. Several popular 0 K methods are summarized: master-slave coupling, ONIOM, the Bridging Domain Method, the Bridging Scale Method and the Quasicontinuum method. The topic of ghost forces in the Bridging Domain Method is studied and the stability properties of Lagrange multiplier coupling methods are reviewed. Several methods for coupling molecular dynamics with continua are described: master-slave and handshake methods, the Bridging Domain Method, and the Bridging Scale Method. The conservation properties of the Bridging Domain Method are demonstrated. Numerical examples are presented which focus on the reduction of spurious phonon reflections from the continuum/molecular interfaces in the Bridging Domain Method. Examples of the simulation of cracks and defects in graphene using a modified ONIOM method to couple continuum, molecular, and quantum subdomain are also given.
Neil Tennant
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199655755
- eISBN:
- 9780191742125
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199655755.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter distinguishes logic as a theory of belief‐statics from our sought account of belief dynamics. The various kinds of belief change are classified. These are: surrendering, adopting or ...
More
This chapter distinguishes logic as a theory of belief‐statics from our sought account of belief dynamics. The various kinds of belief change are classified. These are: surrendering, adopting or switching individual beliefs; and thereby contracting, expanding or revising one’s system of beliefs. Our account of the epistemic norms involved is agent-centric. The idealized figure of the logical paragon (as opposed to the completely fictional figure of the ‘logical saint’) is introduced as the guiding model of a rational agent who is thoroughly competent in matters of belief change. The chapter discusses what a theory of belief change needs to characterize or make feasible. Two key constraints are formulated: both minimal mutilation and minimal bloating of systems of belief undergoing contractions and revisions needs to be explicated (and ensured). The explicit goal is to provide a computationally implementable account of belief change. The chapter foreshadows welcome results to be proved about the computational complexity of the contraction problem. It stresses that our account of belief dynamics will be able to cope with differences among different schools, or ‘‐isms’, in epistemology, regarding permissible global patterns of support or justification among beliefs. The chapter includes an important discussion of methodology, invoking the contrast between propositional and first-order logic as a case study, in order to highlight the virtues of simplicity in formal modeling. This chapter promises to be an account of belief change under judiciously chosen simplifying assumptions that nevertheless allow a rich structure to come into focus, and challenging problems to emerge.Less
This chapter distinguishes logic as a theory of belief‐statics from our sought account of belief dynamics. The various kinds of belief change are classified. These are: surrendering, adopting or switching individual beliefs; and thereby contracting, expanding or revising one’s system of beliefs. Our account of the epistemic norms involved is agent-centric. The idealized figure of the logical paragon (as opposed to the completely fictional figure of the ‘logical saint’) is introduced as the guiding model of a rational agent who is thoroughly competent in matters of belief change. The chapter discusses what a theory of belief change needs to characterize or make feasible. Two key constraints are formulated: both minimal mutilation and minimal bloating of systems of belief undergoing contractions and revisions needs to be explicated (and ensured). The explicit goal is to provide a computationally implementable account of belief change. The chapter foreshadows welcome results to be proved about the computational complexity of the contraction problem. It stresses that our account of belief dynamics will be able to cope with differences among different schools, or ‘‐isms’, in epistemology, regarding permissible global patterns of support or justification among beliefs. The chapter includes an important discussion of methodology, invoking the contrast between propositional and first-order logic as a case study, in order to highlight the virtues of simplicity in formal modeling. This chapter promises to be an account of belief change under judiciously chosen simplifying assumptions that nevertheless allow a rich structure to come into focus, and challenging problems to emerge.
John Hicks
- Published in print:
- 1987
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198772873
- eISBN:
- 9780191596438
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198772874.003.0001
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Macro- and Monetary Economics
This chapter defines the terms methods and models. A method is a family or class of models. A model is a piece of theory, a theoretical construction, which is intended to be applied to a certain ...
More
This chapter defines the terms methods and models. A method is a family or class of models. A model is a piece of theory, a theoretical construction, which is intended to be applied to a certain range of facts. Models may thus be classified according the facts to which they are intended to refer; so there are models of international trade, of labour relations, of the money market, and so on. But a class of models, when the grouping was of this character, would not at all conveniently be called a method. The definition of ‘economic dynamics’ must follow from the definition of ‘economic statics’: when we have defined one, we have defined the other. A static condition is one in which certain key variables (the quantities of commodities that are produced and consumed, and the prices at which they are exchanged) are unchanging. A dynamic condition is then, by inevitable opposition, one in which they are changing; and dynamic theory is the analysis of the processes by which they change.Less
This chapter defines the terms methods and models. A method is a family or class of models. A model is a piece of theory, a theoretical construction, which is intended to be applied to a certain range of facts. Models may thus be classified according the facts to which they are intended to refer; so there are models of international trade, of labour relations, of the money market, and so on. But a class of models, when the grouping was of this character, would not at all conveniently be called a method. The definition of ‘economic dynamics’ must follow from the definition of ‘economic statics’: when we have defined one, we have defined the other. A static condition is one in which certain key variables (the quantities of commodities that are produced and consumed, and the prices at which they are exchanged) are unchanging. A dynamic condition is then, by inevitable opposition, one in which they are changing; and dynamic theory is the analysis of the processes by which they change.
Geoffrey Brennan and Philip Pettit
- Published in print:
- 2004
- Published Online:
- November 2004
- ISBN:
- 9780199246489
- eISBN:
- 9780191601460
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199246483.003.0006
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Microeconomics
How A scores in the esteem stakes depends on the assessment of A’s performance relative to standards. The higher the standards the greater the incentive to perform well, other things equal. But ...
More
How A scores in the esteem stakes depends on the assessment of A’s performance relative to standards. The higher the standards the greater the incentive to perform well, other things equal. But standards themselves reflect prevailing practice. So there is a feedback loop between performance and standards in any estimable domain. The aim of this chapter is to explore this feedback loop by constructing a simple equilibrium in the performance domain. Even if esteem is not ‘positional’ in the sense that it is awarded on the basis of one’s ranking, esteem exhibits zero-sum properties in the simplest cases. This fact raises questions about the normative properties of esteem-seeking behaviour.Less
How A scores in the esteem stakes depends on the assessment of A’s performance relative to standards. The higher the standards the greater the incentive to perform well, other things equal. But standards themselves reflect prevailing practice. So there is a feedback loop between performance and standards in any estimable domain. The aim of this chapter is to explore this feedback loop by constructing a simple equilibrium in the performance domain. Even if esteem is not ‘positional’ in the sense that it is awarded on the basis of one’s ranking, esteem exhibits zero-sum properties in the simplest cases. This fact raises questions about the normative properties of esteem-seeking behaviour.
Michio Morishima
- Published in print:
- 1963
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198281450
- eISBN:
- 9780191596650
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198281455.003.0001
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Development, Growth, and Environmental
This chapter discusses formal similarities between the exchange equilibrium under weak gross substitutability and the static input–output system as represented by various Leontief‐type models. By ...
More
This chapter discusses formal similarities between the exchange equilibrium under weak gross substitutability and the static input–output system as represented by various Leontief‐type models. By algebraic operations alone (no infinite processes being used), it is seen that the Hicksian laws of comparative statics and the Le Chatelier–Samuelson principle hold in both systems.Less
This chapter discusses formal similarities between the exchange equilibrium under weak gross substitutability and the static input–output system as represented by various Leontief‐type models. By algebraic operations alone (no infinite processes being used), it is seen that the Hicksian laws of comparative statics and the Le Chatelier–Samuelson principle hold in both systems.
Martin Meisel
- Published in print:
- 2007
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199215492
- eISBN:
- 9780191695957
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199215492.003.0016
- Subject:
- Literature, Drama
Duration and location are features of performance; time and place are intrinsic to the play. Of the latter two, place would seem the simpler matter, as less essentially ‘dramatic’. The dramatic uses ...
More
Duration and location are features of performance; time and place are intrinsic to the play. Of the latter two, place would seem the simpler matter, as less essentially ‘dramatic’. The dramatic uses of time are manifest: in the familiar notion of suspense, for example, where we have to wait and see; in the melodramatic (now cinematic) race against the clock; in the one-thing-leading-to-another succession of events, culminating in revelation or denouement. In contrast, the work of place in the modern theatre tends to be equated with ‘setting’, which suggests torpidity and fixity. This chapter discusses the following topics: statics, dynamics, and place-time.Less
Duration and location are features of performance; time and place are intrinsic to the play. Of the latter two, place would seem the simpler matter, as less essentially ‘dramatic’. The dramatic uses of time are manifest: in the familiar notion of suspense, for example, where we have to wait and see; in the melodramatic (now cinematic) race against the clock; in the one-thing-leading-to-another succession of events, culminating in revelation or denouement. In contrast, the work of place in the modern theatre tends to be equated with ‘setting’, which suggests torpidity and fixity. This chapter discusses the following topics: statics, dynamics, and place-time.
Piers J. Hale
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- January 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780226108490
- eISBN:
- 9780226108520
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226108520.003.0002
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
Following recent scholarship it is clear that Herbert Spencer was no social Darwinist, rather his Lamarckian politics reflected an appreciation of the radicalism of William Godwin and Erasmus Darwin. ...
More
Following recent scholarship it is clear that Herbert Spencer was no social Darwinist, rather his Lamarckian politics reflected an appreciation of the radicalism of William Godwin and Erasmus Darwin. Unlike many Whigs Spencer was ambivalent about Malthus's claim that population would outstrip resources. In his “Theory of Population” Spencer explained that the struggle for existence would drive the development of human intelligence as people exercised and thereby increased their mental capacities. In doing so they would deplete the neurine in their brains. Citing respected contemporary physiologists Spencer believed neurine was the same chemical substance that fuelled sexual desire, thus solving the Malthusian dilemma. In Social Statics and other early works Spencer articulated limited government as the basis of a progressive evolution towards a utopian socialist future, it was only later, when contemporary socialists embraced statist solutions to social problems, that he drew back from these conclusions.Less
Following recent scholarship it is clear that Herbert Spencer was no social Darwinist, rather his Lamarckian politics reflected an appreciation of the radicalism of William Godwin and Erasmus Darwin. Unlike many Whigs Spencer was ambivalent about Malthus's claim that population would outstrip resources. In his “Theory of Population” Spencer explained that the struggle for existence would drive the development of human intelligence as people exercised and thereby increased their mental capacities. In doing so they would deplete the neurine in their brains. Citing respected contemporary physiologists Spencer believed neurine was the same chemical substance that fuelled sexual desire, thus solving the Malthusian dilemma. In Social Statics and other early works Spencer articulated limited government as the basis of a progressive evolution towards a utopian socialist future, it was only later, when contemporary socialists embraced statist solutions to social problems, that he drew back from these conclusions.
Pierre-André Chiappori
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691171739
- eISBN:
- 9781400885732
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691171739.003.0004
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Macro- and Monetary Economics
This chapter considers matching by categories, beginning with a discussion of a specific but empirically very relevant family of models in order to provide a richer representation of heterogeneity ...
More
This chapter considers matching by categories, beginning with a discussion of a specific but empirically very relevant family of models in order to provide a richer representation of heterogeneity between individuals that would account not only for economic aspects such as income or education, as well as more subjective (and less easily observable) ones, such as idiosyncratic preferences for marriage in general and for specific types of spouses in particular. The chapter explores a simple model that describes matching on income or education, the separability assumption, how separability can be justified, and the dual structure under separability. It also provides an overview of the Choo-Siow model, focusing on its basic structure, the matching function, heteroskedasticity, comparative statics, testability and identifiability, and the Galichon and Salanié's cupid framework as an extension of the model.Less
This chapter considers matching by categories, beginning with a discussion of a specific but empirically very relevant family of models in order to provide a richer representation of heterogeneity between individuals that would account not only for economic aspects such as income or education, as well as more subjective (and less easily observable) ones, such as idiosyncratic preferences for marriage in general and for specific types of spouses in particular. The chapter explores a simple model that describes matching on income or education, the separability assumption, how separability can be justified, and the dual structure under separability. It also provides an overview of the Choo-Siow model, focusing on its basic structure, the matching function, heteroskedasticity, comparative statics, testability and identifiability, and the Galichon and Salanié's cupid framework as an extension of the model.
Theodore M. Porter
- Published in print:
- 2021
- Published Online:
- September 2021
- ISBN:
- 9780192844774
- eISBN:
- 9780191933349
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780192844774.003.0008
- Subject:
- History, Cultural History
Statistics achieved something like disciplinary status in universities as a mathematical and methodological field during the first half of the twentieth century. Yet the experience of statistics ...
More
Statistics achieved something like disciplinary status in universities as a mathematical and methodological field during the first half of the twentieth century. Yet the experience of statistics stands as a warning against the supposition that scientific knowledge tends naturally to become a discrete discipline. Centuries prior to the consolidation of the mathematical field of statistics, there arose, gradually, a social and administrative field of statistics. Some of the most fundamental concepts and tools of statistical reasoning were first established in this context. Census offices and statistical bureaus devoted to economic, medical, trade, and labor statistics behave in some ways like scientific fields, and in recent times have been more or less closely allied to the mathematical field. From the late nineteenth century, the mathematical field of statistics also came to be seen as a set of concepts and tools for analyzing data in a variety of fields, from engineering, agriculture, education, medicine, and social surveys to astronomy, psychology, economics, sociology, ecology, and physical sciences. All of these gave some heed to the statistical discipline, but none were quite content to mathematicians and methodologists of quantification who dictate the appropriate tools to be used in diverse substantive disciplines. At the same time, input from the substantive disciplines and even from bureaucratic and professional uses has always been important for the shaping of the statistical discipline, which first took shape primarily as a field devoted to problems of evolution, genetics, and eugenics. That history shows a geographical trajectory, arising most prominently in Britain and spreading most readily to other English-language countries.Less
Statistics achieved something like disciplinary status in universities as a mathematical and methodological field during the first half of the twentieth century. Yet the experience of statistics stands as a warning against the supposition that scientific knowledge tends naturally to become a discrete discipline. Centuries prior to the consolidation of the mathematical field of statistics, there arose, gradually, a social and administrative field of statistics. Some of the most fundamental concepts and tools of statistical reasoning were first established in this context. Census offices and statistical bureaus devoted to economic, medical, trade, and labor statistics behave in some ways like scientific fields, and in recent times have been more or less closely allied to the mathematical field. From the late nineteenth century, the mathematical field of statistics also came to be seen as a set of concepts and tools for analyzing data in a variety of fields, from engineering, agriculture, education, medicine, and social surveys to astronomy, psychology, economics, sociology, ecology, and physical sciences. All of these gave some heed to the statistical discipline, but none were quite content to mathematicians and methodologists of quantification who dictate the appropriate tools to be used in diverse substantive disciplines. At the same time, input from the substantive disciplines and even from bureaucratic and professional uses has always been important for the shaping of the statistical discipline, which first took shape primarily as a field devoted to problems of evolution, genetics, and eugenics. That history shows a geographical trajectory, arising most prominently in Britain and spreading most readily to other English-language countries.
- Published in print:
- 2001
- Published Online:
- March 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780226099064
- eISBN:
- 9780226099088
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226099088.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science
This chapter discusses some of the rhetorical maneuvers that can be discovered through a study of Dobzhansky's text in its social and intellectual context. The tools that Dobzhansky used to amplify ...
More
This chapter discusses some of the rhetorical maneuvers that can be discovered through a study of Dobzhansky's text in its social and intellectual context. The tools that Dobzhansky used to amplify his explanations were thought experiments and the description of experimental or field reports that corroborated the results of the mathematical theories. The rhetorical strategy that Dobzhansky used to introduce these data is called prolepsis, or “anticipatory refutation,” in which an opposition argument is anticipated and directly countered by the rhetoric. Dobzhansky used prolepsis to bring out into the open, and then refute with data from experiments, the arguments against a new evolutionary synthesis that would be offered by skeptical naturalists and geneticists. The semantic distinctions between statics and dynamics show that the dimensions must be combined to create a complete understanding of biology. The former concerns the forces that bring about change in the genetic composition of a population, the latter the interaction of forces in the formation and disintegration of races and species.Less
This chapter discusses some of the rhetorical maneuvers that can be discovered through a study of Dobzhansky's text in its social and intellectual context. The tools that Dobzhansky used to amplify his explanations were thought experiments and the description of experimental or field reports that corroborated the results of the mathematical theories. The rhetorical strategy that Dobzhansky used to introduce these data is called prolepsis, or “anticipatory refutation,” in which an opposition argument is anticipated and directly countered by the rhetoric. Dobzhansky used prolepsis to bring out into the open, and then refute with data from experiments, the arguments against a new evolutionary synthesis that would be offered by skeptical naturalists and geneticists. The semantic distinctions between statics and dynamics show that the dimensions must be combined to create a complete understanding of biology. The former concerns the forces that bring about change in the genetic composition of a population, the latter the interaction of forces in the formation and disintegration of races and species.
Robert G. Chambers
- Published in print:
- 2021
- Published Online:
- December 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780190063016
- eISBN:
- 9780190063047
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780190063016.003.0004
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Econometrics, Microeconomics
Three generic economic optimization problems (expenditure (cost) minimization, revenue maximization, and profit maximization) are studied using the mathematical tools developed in Chapters 2 and 3. ...
More
Three generic economic optimization problems (expenditure (cost) minimization, revenue maximization, and profit maximization) are studied using the mathematical tools developed in Chapters 2 and 3. Conjugate duality results are developed for each. The resulting dual representations (E(q;y), R(p,x), and π(p,q)) are shown to characterize all of the economically relevant information in, respectively, V(y), Y(x), and Gr(≽(y)). The implications of different restrictions on ≽(y) for the dual representations are examined.Less
Three generic economic optimization problems (expenditure (cost) minimization, revenue maximization, and profit maximization) are studied using the mathematical tools developed in Chapters 2 and 3. Conjugate duality results are developed for each. The resulting dual representations (E(q;y), R(p,x), and π(p,q)) are shown to characterize all of the economically relevant information in, respectively, V(y), Y(x), and Gr(≽(y)). The implications of different restrictions on ≽(y) for the dual representations are examined.
Jennifer Coopersmith
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- June 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198743040
- eISBN:
- 9780191802966
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198743040.003.0004
- Subject:
- Physics, Particle Physics / Astrophysics / Cosmology, History of Physics
The meaning behind the mysterious Principle of Virtual Work is explained. Some worked examples in statics (equilibrium) are given, and the method of Virtual Work is compared and contrasted with the ...
More
The meaning behind the mysterious Principle of Virtual Work is explained. Some worked examples in statics (equilibrium) are given, and the method of Virtual Work is compared and contrasted with the method of Newtonian Mechanics. The meaning of virtual displacements is explained very carefully. They must be ‘small’, happen simultaneously, and do not cause a force, result froma force, or take any time to occur. Counter to intuition, not all the actual displacements can be allowed as virtual displacements. Some examples worked through are: Feynman’s pivoting (cantilever) bar, a “black box,” a weighted spring, a ladder, a capacitor, a soap bubble, and Atwood’s machine. The links between mechanics and geometry are demonstrated, and it is shown how the reaction or constraint forces are always perpendicular to the virtual displacements. Lanczos’s Postulate A and its astounding universality are explained.Less
The meaning behind the mysterious Principle of Virtual Work is explained. Some worked examples in statics (equilibrium) are given, and the method of Virtual Work is compared and contrasted with the method of Newtonian Mechanics. The meaning of virtual displacements is explained very carefully. They must be ‘small’, happen simultaneously, and do not cause a force, result froma force, or take any time to occur. Counter to intuition, not all the actual displacements can be allowed as virtual displacements. Some examples worked through are: Feynman’s pivoting (cantilever) bar, a “black box,” a weighted spring, a ladder, a capacitor, a soap bubble, and Atwood’s machine. The links between mechanics and geometry are demonstrated, and it is shown how the reaction or constraint forces are always perpendicular to the virtual displacements. Lanczos’s Postulate A and its astounding universality are explained.
Jeffrey K. McDonough
- Published in print:
- 2022
- Published Online:
- April 2022
- ISBN:
- 9780197629079
- eISBN:
- 9780197629109
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780197629079.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter explores Leibniz’s ingenious treatment of the breaking strength of rigid bodies. In 1684, in a seminal paper published in the Acta Eruditorum, Leibniz offered a model of the behavior of ...
More
This chapter explores Leibniz’s ingenious treatment of the breaking strength of rigid bodies. In 1684, in a seminal paper published in the Acta Eruditorum, Leibniz offered a model of the behavior of rigid bodies that crucially takes it for granted that rigid beams must satisfy his Principle of Optimality. In doing so, he successfully arrived at an improved formula for calculating the strength of a cubic beam. Beyond its scientific results, however, Leibniz’s approach to the problem of determining the breaking strength of rigid beams had profound implications for the structure and nature of matter itself. This chapter draws out the implications of Leibniz’s account for his views on the nature of forces and material bodies. It concludes by considering the implications of Leibniz’s thinking about forces and bodies for his understanding of the relationship between monads and space.Less
This chapter explores Leibniz’s ingenious treatment of the breaking strength of rigid bodies. In 1684, in a seminal paper published in the Acta Eruditorum, Leibniz offered a model of the behavior of rigid bodies that crucially takes it for granted that rigid beams must satisfy his Principle of Optimality. In doing so, he successfully arrived at an improved formula for calculating the strength of a cubic beam. Beyond its scientific results, however, Leibniz’s approach to the problem of determining the breaking strength of rigid beams had profound implications for the structure and nature of matter itself. This chapter draws out the implications of Leibniz’s account for his views on the nature of forces and material bodies. It concludes by considering the implications of Leibniz’s thinking about forces and bodies for his understanding of the relationship between monads and space.
Jeffrey K. McDonough
- Published in print:
- 2022
- Published Online:
- April 2022
- ISBN:
- 9780197629079
- eISBN:
- 9780197629109
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780197629079.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter looks to Leibniz’s work on catenaries—freely hanging cords suspended at both ends—for insight into his understanding of monadic agency. After discussing Leibniz’s understanding of ...
More
This chapter looks to Leibniz’s work on catenaries—freely hanging cords suspended at both ends—for insight into his understanding of monadic agency. After discussing Leibniz’s understanding of catenaries as instances of optimal form, the chapter argues that catenaries provide an especially elegant model for Leibniz’s understanding of monadic agency, a model that helps to resolve otherwise outstanding problems in Leibniz’s thinking about how immaterial mind-like substances may unfold in a goal-directed manner. As a whole, the chapter aims to show how specific features of optimal form may be invoked to provide Leibniz’s views on monadic agency a coherence and elegance that they would otherwise lack.Less
This chapter looks to Leibniz’s work on catenaries—freely hanging cords suspended at both ends—for insight into his understanding of monadic agency. After discussing Leibniz’s understanding of catenaries as instances of optimal form, the chapter argues that catenaries provide an especially elegant model for Leibniz’s understanding of monadic agency, a model that helps to resolve otherwise outstanding problems in Leibniz’s thinking about how immaterial mind-like substances may unfold in a goal-directed manner. As a whole, the chapter aims to show how specific features of optimal form may be invoked to provide Leibniz’s views on monadic agency a coherence and elegance that they would otherwise lack.
Jeffrey K. McDonough
- Published in print:
- 2022
- Published Online:
- April 2022
- ISBN:
- 9780197629079
- eISBN:
- 9780197629109
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780197629079.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter discusses Leibniz’s efforts with respect to the famous problem of the brachistochrone—that is, the problem of determining the shape of the path of quickest descent between two points in ...
More
This chapter discusses Leibniz’s efforts with respect to the famous problem of the brachistochrone—that is, the problem of determining the shape of the path of quickest descent between two points in a vertical plane. After setting the historical stage, the chapter argues that the rational mechanics of the eighteenth century and beyond—developed by the likes of Leonhard Euler, Joseph-Louis Lagrange, and William Rowan Hamilton—served to vindicate Leibniz’s optimality approach to problems in optics, mechanics, and statics. The chapter thus aims to show that Leibniz’s Principle of Optimality has proven itself to be a miracle creed not only in virtue of its odd epistemological standing—in its being fully grounded neither in reason nor experience—but also in having “been borne out to an amazing extent by the development of science.”Less
This chapter discusses Leibniz’s efforts with respect to the famous problem of the brachistochrone—that is, the problem of determining the shape of the path of quickest descent between two points in a vertical plane. After setting the historical stage, the chapter argues that the rational mechanics of the eighteenth century and beyond—developed by the likes of Leonhard Euler, Joseph-Louis Lagrange, and William Rowan Hamilton—served to vindicate Leibniz’s optimality approach to problems in optics, mechanics, and statics. The chapter thus aims to show that Leibniz’s Principle of Optimality has proven itself to be a miracle creed not only in virtue of its odd epistemological standing—in its being fully grounded neither in reason nor experience—but also in having “been borne out to an amazing extent by the development of science.”
Robert T. Hanlon
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- April 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198851547
- eISBN:
- 9780191886133
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198851547.003.0010
- Subject:
- Physics, Theoretical, Computational, and Statistical Physics
Galileo connected the distance of a body’s free fall with the increase in the square of the body’s speed. This experimental finding was later used by Huygens and then Leibniz to establish mv2 as an ...
More
Galileo connected the distance of a body’s free fall with the increase in the square of the body’s speed. This experimental finding was later used by Huygens and then Leibniz to establish mv2 as an important quantity in physics.Less
Galileo connected the distance of a body’s free fall with the increase in the square of the body’s speed. This experimental finding was later used by Huygens and then Leibniz to establish mv2 as an important quantity in physics.
Lawrence A. Boland
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780190274320
- eISBN:
- 9780190274368
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190274320.003.0002
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Macro- and Monetary Economics
This chapter examines the explanatory purpose of building equilibrium models and the need to consider dynamics and disequilibria. It examines Marshall’s two ‘Principles’ of explanation, the ...
More
This chapter examines the explanatory purpose of building equilibrium models and the need to consider dynamics and disequilibria. It examines Marshall’s two ‘Principles’ of explanation, the ‘Principle of Substitution’ (essentially the usual neoclassical premise that every decision maker is a maximizer) and the ‘Principle of Continuity’ (that using the assumption of maximization as a basis for explanation is not possible without a continuous range of options to choose among). Marshall’s main mode of explanation using these Principles is his comparative statics analysis. His version of comparative statics introduces a role for time by distinguishing his long-run from short-run equilibria. With this in mind, the chapter goes further to explain why an equilibrium state implies recognition of disequilibrium dynamics and why equilibrium models must recognize the knowledge necessary for the dynamics of equilibrium attainment.Less
This chapter examines the explanatory purpose of building equilibrium models and the need to consider dynamics and disequilibria. It examines Marshall’s two ‘Principles’ of explanation, the ‘Principle of Substitution’ (essentially the usual neoclassical premise that every decision maker is a maximizer) and the ‘Principle of Continuity’ (that using the assumption of maximization as a basis for explanation is not possible without a continuous range of options to choose among). Marshall’s main mode of explanation using these Principles is his comparative statics analysis. His version of comparative statics introduces a role for time by distinguishing his long-run from short-run equilibria. With this in mind, the chapter goes further to explain why an equilibrium state implies recognition of disequilibrium dynamics and why equilibrium models must recognize the knowledge necessary for the dynamics of equilibrium attainment.
Marc Lange
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- December 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780190269487
- eISBN:
- 9780190269500
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190269487.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, General
This chapter concludes the account of “explanation by constraint,” an important variety of non-causal explanation. It shows how that account applies to the longstanding controversy regarding the ...
More
This chapter concludes the account of “explanation by constraint,” an important variety of non-causal explanation. It shows how that account applies to the longstanding controversy regarding the explanation of the law of nature that governs the composition of forces (the “parallelogram of forces”). Various rival proposed explanations of this law are presented. One rival is Isaac Newton’s and William Thomson’s dynamical explanation. Another rival is a non-causal “explanation by constraint” from statics that appeals to symmetry principles and that was defended by Simeon Denis Poisson, Willliam Whewell, and James Clerk Maxwell. The chief questions addressed are what makes these proposals incompatible rivals (as physicists take them to be) and what would make one of these rivals rather than another correct. The account given in previous chapters of counterfactuals reflecting stronger and weaker grades of necessity underlying explanations by constraint nicely applies to this case. This account of explanations by constraint is compared to accounts of “structural explanations.”Less
This chapter concludes the account of “explanation by constraint,” an important variety of non-causal explanation. It shows how that account applies to the longstanding controversy regarding the explanation of the law of nature that governs the composition of forces (the “parallelogram of forces”). Various rival proposed explanations of this law are presented. One rival is Isaac Newton’s and William Thomson’s dynamical explanation. Another rival is a non-causal “explanation by constraint” from statics that appeals to symmetry principles and that was defended by Simeon Denis Poisson, Willliam Whewell, and James Clerk Maxwell. The chief questions addressed are what makes these proposals incompatible rivals (as physicists take them to be) and what would make one of these rivals rather than another correct. The account given in previous chapters of counterfactuals reflecting stronger and weaker grades of necessity underlying explanations by constraint nicely applies to this case. This account of explanations by constraint is compared to accounts of “structural explanations.”
Christopher J. Berry
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- April 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780199560677
- eISBN:
- 9780191761300
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199560677.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter examines a key focal characteristic of the Scottish Enlightenment, namely, its delineation of how a ‘science of man’ can inform and structure an account of ‘society’. The key ...
More
This chapter examines a key focal characteristic of the Scottish Enlightenment, namely, its delineation of how a ‘science of man’ can inform and structure an account of ‘society’. The key contribution of the Scots to the rise of the human sciences lies in a conception of society as a set of interlocked institutions and behaviours. The Scots provided an analysis of both social statics and social dynamics, which shifted the focus away from the individualism that characterized early modern jurisprudence. Humans as social beings are best understood in society and not as monadic individuals. The Scottish analysis also sidelined the centrality traditionally allotted to the political. Humans are social as well as political animals. Political institutions are simply one kind of institution among several, to be given no greater priority than the rest.Less
This chapter examines a key focal characteristic of the Scottish Enlightenment, namely, its delineation of how a ‘science of man’ can inform and structure an account of ‘society’. The key contribution of the Scots to the rise of the human sciences lies in a conception of society as a set of interlocked institutions and behaviours. The Scots provided an analysis of both social statics and social dynamics, which shifted the focus away from the individualism that characterized early modern jurisprudence. Humans as social beings are best understood in society and not as monadic individuals. The Scottish analysis also sidelined the centrality traditionally allotted to the political. Humans are social as well as political animals. Political institutions are simply one kind of institution among several, to be given no greater priority than the rest.
David Jon Furbish
- Published in print:
- 1997
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780195077018
- eISBN:
- 9780197560358
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780195077018.003.0010
- Subject:
- Earth Sciences and Geography, Geophysics: Earth Sciences
Fluid statics concerns the behavior of fluids that possess no linear acceleration within a global (Earth) coordinate system. This includes fluids at rest as well as fluids possessing steady motion ...
More
Fluid statics concerns the behavior of fluids that possess no linear acceleration within a global (Earth) coordinate system. This includes fluids at rest as well as fluids possessing steady motion such that no net forces exist. Such motions may include steady linear motion within the global coordinate system as well as rotation with constant angular velocity about a fixed vertical axis. In this latter case, centrifugal forces must be balanced by centripetal forces (which arise, for example, from a pressure gradient acting toward the axis of rotation). Moreover, we assert that no relative motion between adjacent fluid elements exists. Fluid motion, if present, is therefore like that of a rigid body. In addition, we neglect molecular motions that lead to mass transport by diffusion. Thus, the idea of a static fluid is a macroscopic one. The developments in this chapter clarify how pressure varies with coordinate position in a static fluid. Both compressible and incompressible fluids are treated. In the simplest case in which the density of a fluid is constant, we will see that pressure varies linearly with vertical position in the fluid according to the hydrostatic equation. In addition, we will consider the possibility that fluid density is not constant. Then, variations in density must be taken into account when computing the pressure at a given position in a fluid column; the pressure arising from the weight of the overlying fluid no longer varies linearly with depth. In the case of an isothermal fluid, whose temperature is constant throughout, any variation in density must arise purely from the compressible behavior of the fluid in response to variations in pressure. In the case where temperature varies with position, fluid density may vary with both pressure and temperature. We will in this regard consider the case of a thermally stratified fluid whose temperature varies only with the vertical coordinate direction. Because fluid statics requires treating how fluid temperature, pressure, and density are related, the developments below make use of thermodynamical principles developed in Chapter 4.
Less
Fluid statics concerns the behavior of fluids that possess no linear acceleration within a global (Earth) coordinate system. This includes fluids at rest as well as fluids possessing steady motion such that no net forces exist. Such motions may include steady linear motion within the global coordinate system as well as rotation with constant angular velocity about a fixed vertical axis. In this latter case, centrifugal forces must be balanced by centripetal forces (which arise, for example, from a pressure gradient acting toward the axis of rotation). Moreover, we assert that no relative motion between adjacent fluid elements exists. Fluid motion, if present, is therefore like that of a rigid body. In addition, we neglect molecular motions that lead to mass transport by diffusion. Thus, the idea of a static fluid is a macroscopic one. The developments in this chapter clarify how pressure varies with coordinate position in a static fluid. Both compressible and incompressible fluids are treated. In the simplest case in which the density of a fluid is constant, we will see that pressure varies linearly with vertical position in the fluid according to the hydrostatic equation. In addition, we will consider the possibility that fluid density is not constant. Then, variations in density must be taken into account when computing the pressure at a given position in a fluid column; the pressure arising from the weight of the overlying fluid no longer varies linearly with depth. In the case of an isothermal fluid, whose temperature is constant throughout, any variation in density must arise purely from the compressible behavior of the fluid in response to variations in pressure. In the case where temperature varies with position, fluid density may vary with both pressure and temperature. We will in this regard consider the case of a thermally stratified fluid whose temperature varies only with the vertical coordinate direction. Because fluid statics requires treating how fluid temperature, pressure, and density are related, the developments below make use of thermodynamical principles developed in Chapter 4.