James Halteman and Edd Noell
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- May 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199763702
- eISBN:
- 9780199932252
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199763702.003.0007
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Financial Economics
Is economics like car building or car repair? Are we working toward a finished product, or are we attempting to answer pertinent questions that arise and change from time to time? These questions are ...
More
Is economics like car building or car repair? Are we working toward a finished product, or are we attempting to answer pertinent questions that arise and change from time to time? These questions are entertained in this chapter in order to explore the nature of the methods economists employ. The subjective nature of data and the relevance of predicting from past trendsis explored. The proof that rational choice analysis predicts better than any alternative process is seen to be less than definitive by typical standards of proof. Welfare economics comes closest to philosophy when it optimizes social welfare with a social welfare function, but the ramifications of that model are rarely explored. Finally, it is suggested that key questions change and economic thinking then adapts to deal with the new challenges. The vignette for this chapter looks at John Maynard Keynes and his rethinking of mainstream macroeconomics.Less
Is economics like car building or car repair? Are we working toward a finished product, or are we attempting to answer pertinent questions that arise and change from time to time? These questions are entertained in this chapter in order to explore the nature of the methods economists employ. The subjective nature of data and the relevance of predicting from past trendsis explored. The proof that rational choice analysis predicts better than any alternative process is seen to be less than definitive by typical standards of proof. Welfare economics comes closest to philosophy when it optimizes social welfare with a social welfare function, but the ramifications of that model are rarely explored. Finally, it is suggested that key questions change and economic thinking then adapts to deal with the new challenges. The vignette for this chapter looks at John Maynard Keynes and his rethinking of mainstream macroeconomics.
Michio Morishima
- Published in print:
- 1969
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198281641
- eISBN:
- 9780191596667
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198281641.003.0009
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Development, Growth, and Environmental
Devoted to establishing the optimality of competitive equilibrium paths of various orders. So far three kinds of equilibrium growth paths have been discussed in the book: the Cassel–von Neumann path ...
More
Devoted to establishing the optimality of competitive equilibrium paths of various orders. So far three kinds of equilibrium growth paths have been discussed in the book: the Cassel–von Neumann path of balanced growth, the Lindahl–Hicks sequence of temporary equilibria, and the Hicks–Malinvaud perfect equilibrium over time. These are now examined for efficiency and optimality. Each of them is compared with any other in succession. The different sections of the chapter discuss definitions of efficiency and Pareto optimality, short‐run efficiency of temporary equilibrium and long‐run efficiency of full equilibrium, Pareto optimality of the Lindahl–Hicks and the Hicks–Malinvaud path, Farkas’ theorem of linear inequalities, the fact that shadow prices associated with a Pareto optimum obey the rules of competitive pricing, the conditions that should be satisfied in order for a given point of Pareto optimum to be a competitive equilibrium, and the Golden Rule of Accumulation.Less
Devoted to establishing the optimality of competitive equilibrium paths of various orders. So far three kinds of equilibrium growth paths have been discussed in the book: the Cassel–von Neumann path of balanced growth, the Lindahl–Hicks sequence of temporary equilibria, and the Hicks–Malinvaud perfect equilibrium over time. These are now examined for efficiency and optimality. Each of them is compared with any other in succession. The different sections of the chapter discuss definitions of efficiency and Pareto optimality, short‐run efficiency of temporary equilibrium and long‐run efficiency of full equilibrium, Pareto optimality of the Lindahl–Hicks and the Hicks–Malinvaud path, Farkas’ theorem of linear inequalities, the fact that shadow prices associated with a Pareto optimum obey the rules of competitive pricing, the conditions that should be satisfied in order for a given point of Pareto optimum to be a competitive equilibrium, and the Golden Rule of Accumulation.
Jules L. Coleman
- Published in print:
- 2002
- Published Online:
- January 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199253609
- eISBN:
- 9780191719783
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199253609.003.0003
- Subject:
- Law, Competition Law
This chapter distinguishes between Pareto optimality, Pareto superiority, and Kaldor-Hicks efficiency, and provides an extended discussion of the Coase theorem. One of the central claims in this ...
More
This chapter distinguishes between Pareto optimality, Pareto superiority, and Kaldor-Hicks efficiency, and provides an extended discussion of the Coase theorem. One of the central claims in this chapter is that the economic analysis of law relies largely on the Kaldor-Hicks criterion of efficiency, less on Pareto optimality, and almost not at all on Pareto superiority. This is important, especially from a normative point of view. What justifies the use of public power, that is, courts, legislatures and administrative agencies, in pursuing efficiency? In his essay Theory of Negligence, Richard Posner shows that a large number of negligence cases were decided along lines of economic efficiency.Less
This chapter distinguishes between Pareto optimality, Pareto superiority, and Kaldor-Hicks efficiency, and provides an extended discussion of the Coase theorem. One of the central claims in this chapter is that the economic analysis of law relies largely on the Kaldor-Hicks criterion of efficiency, less on Pareto optimality, and almost not at all on Pareto superiority. This is important, especially from a normative point of view. What justifies the use of public power, that is, courts, legislatures and administrative agencies, in pursuing efficiency? In his essay Theory of Negligence, Richard Posner shows that a large number of negligence cases were decided along lines of economic efficiency.
Amartya Sen
- Published in print:
- 1973
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198281931
- eISBN:
- 9780191715815
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198281935.003.0001
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Public and Welfare
The usefulness of the main schools of welfare economics (old and new) in measuring inequality is analysed. It is noted that the literature on Pareto optimality avoids distributional judgements ...
More
The usefulness of the main schools of welfare economics (old and new) in measuring inequality is analysed. It is noted that the literature on Pareto optimality avoids distributional judgements altogether, and that the standard social welfare functions approach also fails to provide a framework for distributional discussions because of its concentration on individual orderings only. Utilitarianism (the dominant faith of ‘old’ welfare economics), is too concerned with the welfare sum to be concerned with the problem of distribution and can produce strongly anti‐egalitarian results. Hence, the use of welfare economics for measuring inequality is rejected.Less
The usefulness of the main schools of welfare economics (old and new) in measuring inequality is analysed. It is noted that the literature on Pareto optimality avoids distributional judgements altogether, and that the standard social welfare functions approach also fails to provide a framework for distributional discussions because of its concentration on individual orderings only. Utilitarianism (the dominant faith of ‘old’ welfare economics), is too concerned with the welfare sum to be concerned with the problem of distribution and can produce strongly anti‐egalitarian results. Hence, the use of welfare economics for measuring inequality is rejected.
Peter Dietsch
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- August 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780190251512
- eISBN:
- 9780190251543
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190251512.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Political Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
The concept of efficiency is used in different ways in economics. First, the practical relevance of models that conclude that tax competition is either Pareto optimal or not is limited, because we do ...
More
The concept of efficiency is used in different ways in economics. First, the practical relevance of models that conclude that tax competition is either Pareto optimal or not is limited, because we do not live in the idealized circumstances of the Pareto frontier. Second, the more relevant criterion of Pareto improvement is silent on the prospect of regulating tax competition because, as previous chapters have shown, the latter has redistributive effects. Third, efficiency as an instrumental value to arbitrate trade-offs between two or more policy goals—a role it plays in optimal tax theory, for example—can in fact be used to show that regulating tax competition is a requirement of efficiency rather than an obstacle to it.Less
The concept of efficiency is used in different ways in economics. First, the practical relevance of models that conclude that tax competition is either Pareto optimal or not is limited, because we do not live in the idealized circumstances of the Pareto frontier. Second, the more relevant criterion of Pareto improvement is silent on the prospect of regulating tax competition because, as previous chapters have shown, the latter has redistributive effects. Third, efficiency as an instrumental value to arbitrate trade-offs between two or more policy goals—a role it plays in optimal tax theory, for example—can in fact be used to show that regulating tax competition is a requirement of efficiency rather than an obstacle to it.
Michio Morishima
- Published in print:
- 1969
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198281641
- eISBN:
- 9780191596667
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198281641.003.0015
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Development, Growth, and Environmental
The argument developed in the previous chapter was based on the tacit assumption that the production of goods by means of goods and labour is independent of the feeding of labour, and was described ...
More
The argument developed in the previous chapter was based on the tacit assumption that the production of goods by means of goods and labour is independent of the feeding of labour, and was described in terms of the matrices of input and output coefficients and the vector of labour‐input coefficients, all of which were considered as technologically given constants. However, it is difficult to obtain precise figures of these coefficients, especially for the labour‐input coefficients, without knowing how and at what level people are fed; the productivity of labour depends not only on technology in the narrowest sense but also on the workers’ state of health, their living and working conditions, etc. Further, in a slave economy, with the wages fixed at a subsistence level, the productivity of labour was low, and it is this that led to its replacement by a more productive system—the capitalist economy. It is not surprising that outputs of goods might increase, even though the allocation of available goods among industries and families became unfavourable for the former; in fact, the positive indirect effect on outputs of a transfer of goods from industries to families causing an improvement in the welfare of the workers might be so strong as to overcome the negative direct effect on outputs of the decrease in industrial inputs. Thus, the production of goods and the feeding of men should be treated as an inseparable process, and this is the approach taken in this chapter, which discusses: the production of goods and ‘men’ by means of goods and ‘men’; the properties of aggregate production processes; conditions for the Silvery Equilibrium; modification of the rule of competitive pricing such that Keynesian involuntary unemployment is allowed for; the existence of ‘quasi‐equilibrium’ processes and prices; the upper semicontinuity of quasi‐equilibrium prices; the equilibration of quasi‐equilibrium; efficiency and optimality in an economy with a flexible labour force; instantaneous efficiency and Pareto optimality of the Silvery Equilibrium; the possibility of optimum cyclical growth of production of goods and men; and the intertemporal efficiency and Pareto optimality of the Golden Equilibrium.Less
The argument developed in the previous chapter was based on the tacit assumption that the production of goods by means of goods and labour is independent of the feeding of labour, and was described in terms of the matrices of input and output coefficients and the vector of labour‐input coefficients, all of which were considered as technologically given constants. However, it is difficult to obtain precise figures of these coefficients, especially for the labour‐input coefficients, without knowing how and at what level people are fed; the productivity of labour depends not only on technology in the narrowest sense but also on the workers’ state of health, their living and working conditions, etc. Further, in a slave economy, with the wages fixed at a subsistence level, the productivity of labour was low, and it is this that led to its replacement by a more productive system—the capitalist economy. It is not surprising that outputs of goods might increase, even though the allocation of available goods among industries and families became unfavourable for the former; in fact, the positive indirect effect on outputs of a transfer of goods from industries to families causing an improvement in the welfare of the workers might be so strong as to overcome the negative direct effect on outputs of the decrease in industrial inputs. Thus, the production of goods and the feeding of men should be treated as an inseparable process, and this is the approach taken in this chapter, which discusses: the production of goods and ‘men’ by means of goods and ‘men’; the properties of aggregate production processes; conditions for the Silvery Equilibrium; modification of the rule of competitive pricing such that Keynesian involuntary unemployment is allowed for; the existence of ‘quasi‐equilibrium’ processes and prices; the upper semicontinuity of quasi‐equilibrium prices; the equilibration of quasi‐equilibrium; efficiency and optimality in an economy with a flexible labour force; instantaneous efficiency and Pareto optimality of the Silvery Equilibrium; the possibility of optimum cyclical growth of production of goods and men; and the intertemporal efficiency and Pareto optimality of the Golden Equilibrium.
Michio Morishima
- Published in print:
- 1969
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198281641
- eISBN:
- 9780191596667
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198281641.003.0001
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Development, Growth, and Environmental
Introduces multi‐sectoral growth analysis. Mainly devoted to examining a Walrasian general equilibrium model of capital formation on the smallest possible scale. It is assumed that the economy ...
More
Introduces multi‐sectoral growth analysis. Mainly devoted to examining a Walrasian general equilibrium model of capital formation on the smallest possible scale. It is assumed that the economy concerned consists of many firms that are classified into two industries: the consumption‐good industry and the capital‐good industry. It is also assumed (as Walras and Leontief assumed) that there is no possibility of joint production: the consumption‐good industry only produces the consumption goods and the capital‐good industry only the capital goods (later in the book this assumption is shown to be undesirable). The remaining parts of the chapter give further mathematical treatment of the existence of short‐run equilibrium, its uniqueness, its Pareto optimality, and the investment function implied—a neoclassical growth.Less
Introduces multi‐sectoral growth analysis. Mainly devoted to examining a Walrasian general equilibrium model of capital formation on the smallest possible scale. It is assumed that the economy concerned consists of many firms that are classified into two industries: the consumption‐good industry and the capital‐good industry. It is also assumed (as Walras and Leontief assumed) that there is no possibility of joint production: the consumption‐good industry only produces the consumption goods and the capital‐good industry only the capital goods (later in the book this assumption is shown to be undesirable). The remaining parts of the chapter give further mathematical treatment of the existence of short‐run equilibrium, its uniqueness, its Pareto optimality, and the investment function implied—a neoclassical growth.
Agnar Sandmo
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198297987
- eISBN:
- 9780191596858
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/019829798X.003.0002
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Development, Growth, and Environmental
The basic general equilibrium model of resource allocation is extended to take environmental goods and externalities into account. The conditions for social welfare maximization and Pareto optimality ...
More
The basic general equilibrium model of resource allocation is extended to take environmental goods and externalities into account. The conditions for social welfare maximization and Pareto optimality are derived and compared with the characterization of competitive market equilibrium. The optimality conditions are then used to characterize optimal environmental taxes under the simplifying assumption that there are no other distortions in the economy. The analytical framework is generalized to take account of uncertainty and resource allocation over time, and includes discussions of attitudes to risk and time discounting.Less
The basic general equilibrium model of resource allocation is extended to take environmental goods and externalities into account. The conditions for social welfare maximization and Pareto optimality are derived and compared with the characterization of competitive market equilibrium. The optimality conditions are then used to characterize optimal environmental taxes under the simplifying assumption that there are no other distortions in the economy. The analytical framework is generalized to take account of uncertainty and resource allocation over time, and includes discussions of attitudes to risk and time discounting.
Graham K. Taylor and Adrian L. R. Thomas
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- April 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780198566373
- eISBN:
- 9780191779459
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198566373.003.0008
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics, Ornithology
This chapter uses multi-objective optimization theory to examine how natural selection resolves trade-offs among multiple conflicting performance objectives. Because physical constraint is universal, ...
More
This chapter uses multi-objective optimization theory to examine how natural selection resolves trade-offs among multiple conflicting performance objectives. Because physical constraint is universal, it is not usually possible to improve performance in one dimension without degrading performance in another. The optimizing tendency of natural selection is therefore best understood as implementing a constrained multi-objective optimization. Although we cannot, from first principles, predict exactly how natural selection is expected to weight these various performance objectives, it is usually possible to say something qualitative about how the importance of a given performance objective varies with ecology or behaviour. The most natural way to analyse the outcome of the optimization is therefore by using the concept of Pareto optimality, and the concepts of dominated and non-dominated solutions, which avoids the need to identify an explicit weighting function relating fitness to performance. This approach is illustrated by identifying the Pareto sets of soaring birds with respect to different combinations of soaring performance objectives, by mapping the morphospace describing flight morphology to a performance space describing soaring flight performance. The analysis shows that Procellariiformes in general, and albatrosses in particular, are optimized for performance objectives associated with straight-line soaring flight. In contrast, Acciptriformes in general, and vultures in particular, are optimised for performance objectives associated with circling soaring flight. This analysis solves a long-standing puzzle in animal flight research: the question of why all soaring birds are not albatross-shaped. More generally, it provides a way of understanding the astonishing variety of forms found in nature.Less
This chapter uses multi-objective optimization theory to examine how natural selection resolves trade-offs among multiple conflicting performance objectives. Because physical constraint is universal, it is not usually possible to improve performance in one dimension without degrading performance in another. The optimizing tendency of natural selection is therefore best understood as implementing a constrained multi-objective optimization. Although we cannot, from first principles, predict exactly how natural selection is expected to weight these various performance objectives, it is usually possible to say something qualitative about how the importance of a given performance objective varies with ecology or behaviour. The most natural way to analyse the outcome of the optimization is therefore by using the concept of Pareto optimality, and the concepts of dominated and non-dominated solutions, which avoids the need to identify an explicit weighting function relating fitness to performance. This approach is illustrated by identifying the Pareto sets of soaring birds with respect to different combinations of soaring performance objectives, by mapping the morphospace describing flight morphology to a performance space describing soaring flight performance. The analysis shows that Procellariiformes in general, and albatrosses in particular, are optimized for performance objectives associated with straight-line soaring flight. In contrast, Acciptriformes in general, and vultures in particular, are optimised for performance objectives associated with circling soaring flight. This analysis solves a long-standing puzzle in animal flight research: the question of why all soaring birds are not albatross-shaped. More generally, it provides a way of understanding the astonishing variety of forms found in nature.
Gijs van Donselaar
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- September 2009
- ISBN:
- 9780195140392
- eISBN:
- 9780199871483
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195140392.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This chapter discusses an argument that we should nevertheless be committed to equal property rights in external resources, on account of our (broadly liberal) commitment to freedom as a fundamental ...
More
This chapter discusses an argument that we should nevertheless be committed to equal property rights in external resources, on account of our (broadly liberal) commitment to freedom as a fundamental value. In order to demonstrate the problem with this argument, we have to return to the original egalitarian Robinsonade that was invoked to make the case for basic income.Less
This chapter discusses an argument that we should nevertheless be committed to equal property rights in external resources, on account of our (broadly liberal) commitment to freedom as a fundamental value. In order to demonstrate the problem with this argument, we have to return to the original egalitarian Robinsonade that was invoked to make the case for basic income.
Jules L. Coleman
- Published in print:
- 2002
- Published Online:
- January 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199253609
- eISBN:
- 9780191719783
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199253609.003.0011
- Subject:
- Law, Competition Law
This chapter explores the view that, on both economic and moral grounds, unanimity is the preferable voting rule. Unanimity captures the essential Paretian and consensual features of market exchange, ...
More
This chapter explores the view that, on both economic and moral grounds, unanimity is the preferable voting rule. Unanimity captures the essential Paretian and consensual features of market exchange, and is thus uniquely defensible on both market and moral grounds. Departures from unanimity are unavoidable but must be seen as necessary evils. The usual criticism of unanimity is that it unjustifiably favors the status quo. The chapter asks whether unanimity actually bears the relationship to market exchange that its proponents take to justify it uniquely.Less
This chapter explores the view that, on both economic and moral grounds, unanimity is the preferable voting rule. Unanimity captures the essential Paretian and consensual features of market exchange, and is thus uniquely defensible on both market and moral grounds. Departures from unanimity are unavoidable but must be seen as necessary evils. The usual criticism of unanimity is that it unjustifiably favors the status quo. The chapter asks whether unanimity actually bears the relationship to market exchange that its proponents take to justify it uniquely.
Kwame Anthony Appiah
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- September 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780198744283
- eISBN:
- 9780191805691
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198744283.003.0008
- Subject:
- Business and Management, Corporate Governance and Accountability
This chapter discusses the relationship between capitalism and progress and ends with a discussion of three mechanisms for reducing some of the problems associated with markets. A familiar argument ...
More
This chapter discusses the relationship between capitalism and progress and ends with a discussion of three mechanisms for reducing some of the problems associated with markets. A familiar argument says that markets must advance progress under ideal conditions because they guarantee Pareto optimality. It is shown here that for a variety of reasons—among them the incommensurability of values, the incommensurability of persons, and the fact that history matters—Pareto optimality is neither necessary nor sufficient for progress. Capitalism—understood as the pervasive use of markets—appears, under modern conditions, to lead to greater material inequality, butwhat is problematic is (a) the absolute lack of certain basic resources and (b) the social and political inequalities associated with great differences in wealth. These last can be mitigated by the familiar state mechanisms of law regulation and tax incentives, but also by professional business norms sustained by a concern for one’s honor.Less
This chapter discusses the relationship between capitalism and progress and ends with a discussion of three mechanisms for reducing some of the problems associated with markets. A familiar argument says that markets must advance progress under ideal conditions because they guarantee Pareto optimality. It is shown here that for a variety of reasons—among them the incommensurability of values, the incommensurability of persons, and the fact that history matters—Pareto optimality is neither necessary nor sufficient for progress. Capitalism—understood as the pervasive use of markets—appears, under modern conditions, to lead to greater material inequality, butwhat is problematic is (a) the absolute lack of certain basic resources and (b) the social and political inequalities associated with great differences in wealth. These last can be mitigated by the familiar state mechanisms of law regulation and tax incentives, but also by professional business norms sustained by a concern for one’s honor.
Alan Thomas
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- December 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780190602116
- eISBN:
- 9780190602130
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190602116.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Political Philosophy, General
This chapter sets out the details of John Rawls’s theory of justice and explains why his view includes a concern with regulating the “top end” of any distribution. It is not simply concerned with ...
More
This chapter sets out the details of John Rawls’s theory of justice and explains why his view includes a concern with regulating the “top end” of any distribution. It is not simply concerned with maximizing the position of the relatively worst-off. Alternative interpretations of Rawls are discussed and the importance of the assumptions of chain-connectedness and close-knittedness is emphasized. In a just society the interests of different classes will be interconnected, which explains why a property-owning democracy is one of Rawls’s preferred social systems. The chapter discusses both why inequality is bad for its own sake and why it is instrumentally undesirable because of its bad effects. These arguments draw on the importance of positional goods. The account of inequality’s bad effects is extended to its impact on social solidarity and the fracturing of American society along class lines. The chapter concludes by considering issues of transitional justice.Less
This chapter sets out the details of John Rawls’s theory of justice and explains why his view includes a concern with regulating the “top end” of any distribution. It is not simply concerned with maximizing the position of the relatively worst-off. Alternative interpretations of Rawls are discussed and the importance of the assumptions of chain-connectedness and close-knittedness is emphasized. In a just society the interests of different classes will be interconnected, which explains why a property-owning democracy is one of Rawls’s preferred social systems. The chapter discusses both why inequality is bad for its own sake and why it is instrumentally undesirable because of its bad effects. These arguments draw on the importance of positional goods. The account of inequality’s bad effects is extended to its impact on social solidarity and the fracturing of American society along class lines. The chapter concludes by considering issues of transitional justice.
Kenneth J. Arrow
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- September 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780198744283
- eISBN:
- 9780191805691
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198744283.003.0004
- Subject:
- Business and Management, Corporate Governance and Accountability
This chapter lays out some of the ways in which the current capitalist market economy fails to achieve some human needs and its own full potential. It is not intended to be comprehensive. For one, it ...
More
This chapter lays out some of the ways in which the current capitalist market economy fails to achieve some human needs and its own full potential. It is not intended to be comprehensive. For one, it ignores the problems of inequality of income and wealth, which would require a long consideration on its own. The chapter reviews the strengths of the market system and then discusses information incompleteness and asymmetry, limitations of the price system in market clearing, and especially externalities. Climate, the financial industry, and the business cycle are mentioned as instances of problems that the market system is yet to address satisfactorily.Less
This chapter lays out some of the ways in which the current capitalist market economy fails to achieve some human needs and its own full potential. It is not intended to be comprehensive. For one, it ignores the problems of inequality of income and wealth, which would require a long consideration on its own. The chapter reviews the strengths of the market system and then discusses information incompleteness and asymmetry, limitations of the price system in market clearing, and especially externalities. Climate, the financial industry, and the business cycle are mentioned as instances of problems that the market system is yet to address satisfactorily.
Scott Lehmann
- Published in print:
- 1995
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780195089721
- eISBN:
- 9780197560587
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780195089721.003.0011
- Subject:
- Earth Sciences and Geography, Economic Geography
Insofar as arguments for privatization can be read as appealing to general ethical conceptions, they acquire greater depth and, perhaps, respectability. The argument ...
More
Insofar as arguments for privatization can be read as appealing to general ethical conceptions, they acquire greater depth and, perhaps, respectability. The argument from productivity suggests a rule-form of preference utilitarianism: by changing institutions (in this case, by substituting private property rights for collective management of public lands), we’ll promote people’s welfare by enabling them better to satisfy their desires. But we can also glimpse in the recommended institution of private property rights a more Kantian commitment: where I can acquire what’s yours only with your willing consent (and generally in exchange for something of mine you value more), I can’t treat you simply as a means, at least in certain respects. However, in my view, such appeals do little to advance the argument for privatization; on the contrary, they reveal weaknesses in it. The property rights recommended by privatization advocates provide for individual freedom but not for its wise use. They do not help people to treat humanity in their own persons as an end or to form desires worth satisfying. There is an opening here for arguing that privatization is a bad idea, not because the current system, despite appearances, is relatively efficient or the cost of dismantling it is too great, but because what we’d get is inferior in a more basic sense to what we now have. Public land management promises greater protection of our natural and cultural heritage than the market—at least if we can resist the seductive suggestion that it be marketized, i.e., that we aim to allocate the resources of public lands as would an ideal market. Furthermore, the opportunity to define and defend values in public debate rather than simply buying what we happen to prefer (and can afford) is one we should, in our own interests, preserve. It is primarily on such grounds that I oppose privatizing public lands. To get this argument off the ground, we must allow that what I’m interested in can differ from what’s in my interest. I shall spend much of this chapter meeting objections to such a distinction and arguing that the free market can’t be expected to help people take an interest in what’s in their interest.
Less
Insofar as arguments for privatization can be read as appealing to general ethical conceptions, they acquire greater depth and, perhaps, respectability. The argument from productivity suggests a rule-form of preference utilitarianism: by changing institutions (in this case, by substituting private property rights for collective management of public lands), we’ll promote people’s welfare by enabling them better to satisfy their desires. But we can also glimpse in the recommended institution of private property rights a more Kantian commitment: where I can acquire what’s yours only with your willing consent (and generally in exchange for something of mine you value more), I can’t treat you simply as a means, at least in certain respects. However, in my view, such appeals do little to advance the argument for privatization; on the contrary, they reveal weaknesses in it. The property rights recommended by privatization advocates provide for individual freedom but not for its wise use. They do not help people to treat humanity in their own persons as an end or to form desires worth satisfying. There is an opening here for arguing that privatization is a bad idea, not because the current system, despite appearances, is relatively efficient or the cost of dismantling it is too great, but because what we’d get is inferior in a more basic sense to what we now have. Public land management promises greater protection of our natural and cultural heritage than the market—at least if we can resist the seductive suggestion that it be marketized, i.e., that we aim to allocate the resources of public lands as would an ideal market. Furthermore, the opportunity to define and defend values in public debate rather than simply buying what we happen to prefer (and can afford) is one we should, in our own interests, preserve. It is primarily on such grounds that I oppose privatizing public lands. To get this argument off the ground, we must allow that what I’m interested in can differ from what’s in my interest. I shall spend much of this chapter meeting objections to such a distinction and arguing that the free market can’t be expected to help people take an interest in what’s in their interest.