Jerrold Levinson
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- January 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780199206179
- eISBN:
- 9780191709982
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199206179.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics
This essay surveys the range of philosophical problems that can be encompassed under the rubric, emotion in response to art. It details five such problems, according most of its attention to the ...
More
This essay surveys the range of philosophical problems that can be encompassed under the rubric, emotion in response to art. It details five such problems, according most of its attention to the nature of the emotional responses had to art, and the puzzle of emotional responses to fictional entities known to be fictional (what is often labeled ‘the paradox of fiction’). Attention is also given to the puzzle of how people derive satisfaction from art expressive or evocative of negative emotion (what is often labeled ‘the paradox of tragedy’), and to the question of how abstract works of art (such as pieces of instrumental music) manage to express or evoke emotions at all.Less
This essay surveys the range of philosophical problems that can be encompassed under the rubric, emotion in response to art. It details five such problems, according most of its attention to the nature of the emotional responses had to art, and the puzzle of emotional responses to fictional entities known to be fictional (what is often labeled ‘the paradox of fiction’). Attention is also given to the puzzle of how people derive satisfaction from art expressive or evocative of negative emotion (what is often labeled ‘the paradox of tragedy’), and to the question of how abstract works of art (such as pieces of instrumental music) manage to express or evoke emotions at all.
Jenefer Robinson
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- February 2006
- ISBN:
- 9780199263653
- eISBN:
- 9780191603211
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199263655.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics
The argument of Chapter 4 is defended against a number of objections: that not all novels require emotional involvement (true), that we do not in fact react to novels in a bodily way (false), that I ...
More
The argument of Chapter 4 is defended against a number of objections: that not all novels require emotional involvement (true), that we do not in fact react to novels in a bodily way (false), that I ignore authorial manipulation (I don't ), that some emotional responses are inappropriate (they are), and that according to the so-called ‘paradox of fiction’, it is irrational to respond emotionally to fictional characters when we are perfectly aware that they are fictional. The answer to the paradox of fiction is that we process novels both cognitively and affectively. Our instinctive affective appraisal system is indifferent to whether or not stimulus for emotion exists or not. Persons can get emotionally worked up by imagined and remembered events and people as well as by actual people right in front of them.Less
The argument of Chapter 4 is defended against a number of objections: that not all novels require emotional involvement (true), that we do not in fact react to novels in a bodily way (false), that I ignore authorial manipulation (I don't ), that some emotional responses are inappropriate (they are), and that according to the so-called ‘paradox of fiction’, it is irrational to respond emotionally to fictional characters when we are perfectly aware that they are fictional. The answer to the paradox of fiction is that we process novels both cognitively and affectively. Our instinctive affective appraisal system is indifferent to whether or not stimulus for emotion exists or not. Persons can get emotionally worked up by imagined and remembered events and people as well as by actual people right in front of them.
Peter Langland-Hassan
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- September 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198815068
- eISBN:
- 9780191852886
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198815068.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
Further challenges to the idea that sui generis imaginings account for our affective responses to fiction are developed. The chapter then undertakes an extended analysis of the “paradox of ...
More
Further challenges to the idea that sui generis imaginings account for our affective responses to fiction are developed. The chapter then undertakes an extended analysis of the “paradox of fiction”—viz., the claim that it is irrational or inappropriate to respond emotionally to mere fictions—and proposes a novel solution. A number of theorists have held that special features of imagination play a role in resolving the paradox. It is argued that these proposals fail on their own terms and that the paradox can nevertheless be resolved in a way consistent with our emotional reactions to fiction being grounded in beliefs and desires. Coming to terms with the paradox requires both understanding why the “rug-pull” structure of the examples typically used to motivate it are disanalogous to our experience of fictions, and appreciating the specific emotional norms relevant to fiction-appreciation.Less
Further challenges to the idea that sui generis imaginings account for our affective responses to fiction are developed. The chapter then undertakes an extended analysis of the “paradox of fiction”—viz., the claim that it is irrational or inappropriate to respond emotionally to mere fictions—and proposes a novel solution. A number of theorists have held that special features of imagination play a role in resolving the paradox. It is argued that these proposals fail on their own terms and that the paradox can nevertheless be resolved in a way consistent with our emotional reactions to fiction being grounded in beliefs and desires. Coming to terms with the paradox requires both understanding why the “rug-pull” structure of the examples typically used to motivate it are disanalogous to our experience of fictions, and appreciating the specific emotional norms relevant to fiction-appreciation.
Craig Delancey
- Published in print:
- 2002
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780195142716
- eISBN:
- 9780199833153
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195142713.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
The fact that we emote for fictions is incompatible with some cognitivist views of emotions and has therefore received a great deal of attention and been called the paradox of emotion and fiction. I ...
More
The fact that we emote for fictions is incompatible with some cognitivist views of emotions and has therefore received a great deal of attention and been called the paradox of emotion and fiction. I show how the affect program theory offers an explanation of how and why we emote for fictions. Central to this approach, is the idea that the entertainment of content is prior to and more basic than the consideration of whether a content is warranted.Less
The fact that we emote for fictions is incompatible with some cognitivist views of emotions and has therefore received a great deal of attention and been called the paradox of emotion and fiction. I show how the affect program theory offers an explanation of how and why we emote for fictions. Central to this approach, is the idea that the entertainment of content is prior to and more basic than the consideration of whether a content is warranted.
Carolyn Korsmeyer
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- May 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199756940
- eISBN:
- 9780199895212
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199756940.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
The theorists covered in the first chapter are for the most part contemporary, but disgust has a longer history to consider as well, which is the subject of Chapter 2. As aesthetic theory developed ...
More
The theorists covered in the first chapter are for the most part contemporary, but disgust has a longer history to consider as well, which is the subject of Chapter 2. As aesthetic theory developed into its modern form in the eighteenth century, disgust was considered the single emotion excluded from a role in beautiful art that delivers aesthetic pleasure. Luminaries such as Kant, Lessing, and Mendelssohn concurred with the general consensus that arousal of disgust drives out positive aesthetic assessment. This chapter reviews the traditional critique of disgust as well as certain contemporary scholarship on the subject, specifically that of Menninghaus, setting the stage for the consideration of disgust as a mode of aesthetic apprehension.Less
The theorists covered in the first chapter are for the most part contemporary, but disgust has a longer history to consider as well, which is the subject of Chapter 2. As aesthetic theory developed into its modern form in the eighteenth century, disgust was considered the single emotion excluded from a role in beautiful art that delivers aesthetic pleasure. Luminaries such as Kant, Lessing, and Mendelssohn concurred with the general consensus that arousal of disgust drives out positive aesthetic assessment. This chapter reviews the traditional critique of disgust as well as certain contemporary scholarship on the subject, specifically that of Menninghaus, setting the stage for the consideration of disgust as a mode of aesthetic apprehension.
Kathleen Stock
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- September 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199669639
- eISBN:
- 9780191749384
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199669639.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics, Philosophy of Mind
Philosophical aesthetics has increasingly turned towards empirical evidence to settle long-standing questions. Yet, surprisingly, given philosophers’ tendencies to cautious critical analysis, the use ...
More
Philosophical aesthetics has increasingly turned towards empirical evidence to settle long-standing questions. Yet, surprisingly, given philosophers’ tendencies to cautious critical analysis, the use of such evidence is not always inspected as scrupulously as it could be. In this paper, Stock presents a case study illustrating what she takes to be one instance of the misuse of empirical evidence in a current debate within aesthetics: that of the so-called ‘paradox of fiction’. In some relatively recent literature, there has been a shift towards the citing of sub-personal events as a means of attempting to address this problem. In particular, those neurological or other physiological events that accompany imaginative responses to fictional entities are often cited. Yet, Stock argues, there are often flaws in the way empirical evidence is used to support this sort of account.Less
Philosophical aesthetics has increasingly turned towards empirical evidence to settle long-standing questions. Yet, surprisingly, given philosophers’ tendencies to cautious critical analysis, the use of such evidence is not always inspected as scrupulously as it could be. In this paper, Stock presents a case study illustrating what she takes to be one instance of the misuse of empirical evidence in a current debate within aesthetics: that of the so-called ‘paradox of fiction’. In some relatively recent literature, there has been a shift towards the citing of sub-personal events as a means of attempting to address this problem. In particular, those neurological or other physiological events that accompany imaginative responses to fictional entities are often cited. Yet, Stock argues, there are often flaws in the way empirical evidence is used to support this sort of account.
Derek Matravers
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- May 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199647019
- eISBN:
- 9780191779381
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199647019.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics
This book argues that there is no special link between fiction and imagination and that the current consensus in the philosophy of fiction—based in particular on work by Kendall Walton and Gregory ...
More
This book argues that there is no special link between fiction and imagination and that the current consensus in the philosophy of fiction—based in particular on work by Kendall Walton and Gregory Currie—is wrong. It presents an alternative account, arguing that the distinction between engaging with something via a representation (‘a representation-relation’) and engaging with something face-to-face (‘a confrontation-relation’) is fundamental and the distinction between fictions and non-fictions is relatively insignificant. It provides an alternative account of our engaging with representations, whether fiction or non-fiction, based on the idea that readers construct mental models. In the course of the discussion various puzzles are solved or dissolved, including the (so-called) ‘paradox of fiction’ and the (so-called) ‘problem of imaginative resistance’. Light is also thrown on the issues of elusive narrators and on our engaging with impossible fictions. Finally, it is shown to be a mistake to link the imagination with our engaging with film.Less
This book argues that there is no special link between fiction and imagination and that the current consensus in the philosophy of fiction—based in particular on work by Kendall Walton and Gregory Currie—is wrong. It presents an alternative account, arguing that the distinction between engaging with something via a representation (‘a representation-relation’) and engaging with something face-to-face (‘a confrontation-relation’) is fundamental and the distinction between fictions and non-fictions is relatively insignificant. It provides an alternative account of our engaging with representations, whether fiction or non-fiction, based on the idea that readers construct mental models. In the course of the discussion various puzzles are solved or dissolved, including the (so-called) ‘paradox of fiction’ and the (so-called) ‘problem of imaginative resistance’. Light is also thrown on the issues of elusive narrators and on our engaging with impossible fictions. Finally, it is shown to be a mistake to link the imagination with our engaging with film.
Derek Matravers
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- May 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199647019
- eISBN:
- 9780191779381
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199647019.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics
This chapter argues that, in as much as the ‘paradox of fiction’ is a problem, it is neither a paradox nor about fiction. Colin Radford’s original formulation of the problem is considered and ...
More
This chapter argues that, in as much as the ‘paradox of fiction’ is a problem, it is neither a paradox nor about fiction. Colin Radford’s original formulation of the problem is considered and dismissed, on the grounds that the claim that emotions requires beliefs in the reality of their objects is not even prima facie plausible (and it is not clear that anyone has ever held it to be plausible). Two problems remain. First, Walton has identified a problem, but that it is a problem for representations rather than for fictions. Second, confrontation relations require a different treatment from representation relations. The first problem is solved by denying that people in representations do feel emotions for themselves, and the second problem is merely a special instance of the problem of intentional objects.Less
This chapter argues that, in as much as the ‘paradox of fiction’ is a problem, it is neither a paradox nor about fiction. Colin Radford’s original formulation of the problem is considered and dismissed, on the grounds that the claim that emotions requires beliefs in the reality of their objects is not even prima facie plausible (and it is not clear that anyone has ever held it to be plausible). Two problems remain. First, Walton has identified a problem, but that it is a problem for representations rather than for fictions. Second, confrontation relations require a different treatment from representation relations. The first problem is solved by denying that people in representations do feel emotions for themselves, and the second problem is merely a special instance of the problem of intentional objects.