C. D. C. Reeve
- Published in print:
- 1995
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198235651
- eISBN:
- 9780191679094
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198235651.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This book provides an exploration of the epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological foundations of the Nicomachean Ethics. Rejecting current orthodoxy, this book argues that ...
More
This book provides an exploration of the epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological foundations of the Nicomachean Ethics. Rejecting current orthodoxy, this book argues that scientific-knowledge (episteme) is possible in ethics, that dialectic and understanding (nous) play essentially the same role in ethics as in an Aristotelian science, and that the distinctive role of practical wisdom (phronēsis) is to use the knowledge of universals provided by science, dialectic, and understanding so as best to promote happiness (eudaimonia) in particular circumstances and to ensure a happy life. Turning to happiness itself, the book develops a new account of Aristotle's views on ends and functions, exposing their twofold nature. It argues that the activation of theoretical wisdom is primary happiness, and that the activation of practical wisdom — when it is for the sake of primary happiness — is happiness of a second kind. He concludes with an account of the virtues of character, external goods, and friends, and their place in the happy life.Less
This book provides an exploration of the epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological foundations of the Nicomachean Ethics. Rejecting current orthodoxy, this book argues that scientific-knowledge (episteme) is possible in ethics, that dialectic and understanding (nous) play essentially the same role in ethics as in an Aristotelian science, and that the distinctive role of practical wisdom (phronēsis) is to use the knowledge of universals provided by science, dialectic, and understanding so as best to promote happiness (eudaimonia) in particular circumstances and to ensure a happy life. Turning to happiness itself, the book develops a new account of Aristotle's views on ends and functions, exposing their twofold nature. It argues that the activation of theoretical wisdom is primary happiness, and that the activation of practical wisdom — when it is for the sake of primary happiness — is happiness of a second kind. He concludes with an account of the virtues of character, external goods, and friends, and their place in the happy life.
C. D. C. REEVE
- Published in print:
- 1995
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198235651
- eISBN:
- 9780191679094
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198235651.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This introductory chapter begins with a brief account of the genesis of this book, which seeks to elucidate the epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological foundations of Aristotle's Nicomachean ...
More
This introductory chapter begins with a brief account of the genesis of this book, which seeks to elucidate the epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological foundations of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics by showing (or, in some cases, sketching) its place in the context of Aristotle's broader philosophical enterprise. It then presents an overview of the book's four main chapters, representing four related perspectives on phronēsis and nous and their interrelations, which together lay bear the foundations — epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological — on which the Nicomachean Ethics is built.Less
This introductory chapter begins with a brief account of the genesis of this book, which seeks to elucidate the epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological foundations of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics by showing (or, in some cases, sketching) its place in the context of Aristotle's broader philosophical enterprise. It then presents an overview of the book's four main chapters, representing four related perspectives on phronēsis and nous and their interrelations, which together lay bear the foundations — epistemological, metaphysical, and psychological — on which the Nicomachean Ethics is built.
J. Warren Smith
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- January 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780195369939
- eISBN:
- 9780199893362
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195369939.003.0003
- Subject:
- Religion, Theology
Having argued in Chapter 1 that for Ambrose the divisive tension between the soul and the body is not the proper relationship as God intended it in creation, but is the result of the fall, this ...
More
Having argued in Chapter 1 that for Ambrose the divisive tension between the soul and the body is not the proper relationship as God intended it in creation, but is the result of the fall, this chapter examines Ambrose’s understanding of the proper relationship between soul and body. It is argued that Ambrose subscribes to a hylomorphic anthropology akin to that of both Aristotle and Plotinus. Yet given his commitment to the immortality of the soul, Ambrose’s view is closer to Plotinus than Aristotle. This hylomorphic anthropology provides a model for understanding Ambrose’s view of human emotions or passions.Less
Having argued in Chapter 1 that for Ambrose the divisive tension between the soul and the body is not the proper relationship as God intended it in creation, but is the result of the fall, this chapter examines Ambrose’s understanding of the proper relationship between soul and body. It is argued that Ambrose subscribes to a hylomorphic anthropology akin to that of both Aristotle and Plotinus. Yet given his commitment to the immortality of the soul, Ambrose’s view is closer to Plotinus than Aristotle. This hylomorphic anthropology provides a model for understanding Ambrose’s view of human emotions or passions.
Martin Laird
- Published in print:
- 2004
- Published Online:
- November 2004
- ISBN:
- 9780199267996
- eISBN:
- 9780191601576
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199267995.001.0001
- Subject:
- Religion, Early Christian Studies
Discusses Gregory’s understanding of faith (pistis) as a faculty of apophatic union with God. After presenting an overview of important work done on Gregory’s understanding of faith and announcing ...
More
Discusses Gregory’s understanding of faith (pistis) as a faculty of apophatic union with God. After presenting an overview of important work done on Gregory’s understanding of faith and announcing the lines of argument the will pursue, we analyse how Gregory views the mind and its varying cognitive states, and how the mind responds to scripture, baptism, and the presence of God. This is followed by a detailed examination of Gregory’s use of the word ‘faith’ as a technical term for apophatic union with God. This apophatic union, however, is only one side of this coin: at the apex of an apophatic ascent, faith unites with God the Word, but by virtue of this union the believer takes on the qualities of the Word, who speaks (logophasis) in the deeds and discourse of the believer. Finally, this study redresses Gregory’s over-identification with a ‘mysticism of darkness’ and shows that he proposes no less a ‘mysticism of light’.Less
Discusses Gregory’s understanding of faith (pistis) as a faculty of apophatic union with God. After presenting an overview of important work done on Gregory’s understanding of faith and announcing the lines of argument the will pursue, we analyse how Gregory views the mind and its varying cognitive states, and how the mind responds to scripture, baptism, and the presence of God. This is followed by a detailed examination of Gregory’s use of the word ‘faith’ as a technical term for apophatic union with God. This apophatic union, however, is only one side of this coin: at the apex of an apophatic ascent, faith unites with God the Word, but by virtue of this union the believer takes on the qualities of the Word, who speaks (logophasis) in the deeds and discourse of the believer. Finally, this study redresses Gregory’s over-identification with a ‘mysticism of darkness’ and shows that he proposes no less a ‘mysticism of light’.
Frisbee C. C. Sheffield
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- September 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780199286775
- eISBN:
- 9780191713194
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199286775.003.0005
- Subject:
- Classical Studies, Ancient Greek, Roman, and Early Christian Philosophy
This chapter explores Socrates argument for the proper activity of eros: philosophical activity. Since eudaimonia is the aim of all eros and its proper end (telos), our choice of good must be one ...
More
This chapter explores Socrates argument for the proper activity of eros: philosophical activity. Since eudaimonia is the aim of all eros and its proper end (telos), our choice of good must be one that will satisfy this desire: it must be a good whose possession no longer requires us to ask of the agent what she wants in pursuing it, something desired for its own sake, a final good. It is argued that the issue that structures the division of the productive activities of different desiring agents into the lower and higher mysteries is what we might term a division of ends. The desiring agents of the lower mysteries pursue things that are chosen for the sake of something higher, whilst the desiring agent of the higher mysteries pursues that which is chosen for its own sake. The chapter goes on to give some content to this idea, and argues that contemplation of a supremely valuable object — the Form of beauty — satisfies the criterion for being a final good. Contemplative activity is not desired for anything beyond itself, and it is a secure good in the sense that it is true, and a state of the agent's own soul, not dependent on external events for its possession. It is also the fulfilment of our nature and godlike.Less
This chapter explores Socrates argument for the proper activity of eros: philosophical activity. Since eudaimonia is the aim of all eros and its proper end (telos), our choice of good must be one that will satisfy this desire: it must be a good whose possession no longer requires us to ask of the agent what she wants in pursuing it, something desired for its own sake, a final good. It is argued that the issue that structures the division of the productive activities of different desiring agents into the lower and higher mysteries is what we might term a division of ends. The desiring agents of the lower mysteries pursue things that are chosen for the sake of something higher, whilst the desiring agent of the higher mysteries pursues that which is chosen for its own sake. The chapter goes on to give some content to this idea, and argues that contemplation of a supremely valuable object — the Form of beauty — satisfies the criterion for being a final good. Contemplative activity is not desired for anything beyond itself, and it is a secure good in the sense that it is true, and a state of the agent's own soul, not dependent on external events for its possession. It is also the fulfilment of our nature and godlike.
Bruce Rosenstock
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- September 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199545544
- eISBN:
- 9780191720598
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199545544.003.0010
- Subject:
- Classical Studies, Literary Studies: Classical, Early, and Medieval
There are two discussions of Aristotle that can be taken as bookends in the Derridean corpus: ‘White Mythology: Metaphor in the Text of Philosophy’ (1972) and Politics of Friendship (1994). This ...
More
There are two discussions of Aristotle that can be taken as bookends in the Derridean corpus: ‘White Mythology: Metaphor in the Text of Philosophy’ (1972) and Politics of Friendship (1994). This article argues that Derrida's departure from and return to Aristotle follows the narrative logic of an Odyssean nostos whose Indo‐European, ‘white mythological’, provenance is precisely the solar myth of the dying and reborn sun and whose root nes‐* (‘return to light and life’) also lies behind the noun nous. Derrida resists the safe nostos of a philosophical nous that seeks only an unerring return voyage to its point of origin. Derrida's nostos, although it is charted between Occident (Greek) and Orient (Jew), embraces the errancy of a voyage with neither a fixed origin nor a final destination.Less
There are two discussions of Aristotle that can be taken as bookends in the Derridean corpus: ‘White Mythology: Metaphor in the Text of Philosophy’ (1972) and Politics of Friendship (1994). This article argues that Derrida's departure from and return to Aristotle follows the narrative logic of an Odyssean nostos whose Indo‐European, ‘white mythological’, provenance is precisely the solar myth of the dying and reborn sun and whose root nes‐* (‘return to light and life’) also lies behind the noun nous. Derrida resists the safe nostos of a philosophical nous that seeks only an unerring return voyage to its point of origin. Derrida's nostos, although it is charted between Occident (Greek) and Orient (Jew), embraces the errancy of a voyage with neither a fixed origin nor a final destination.
C. C. W. Taylor
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- May 2008
- ISBN:
- 9780199226399
- eISBN:
- 9780191710209
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199226399.003.0012
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy
This chapter examines the role of the practical intellect in Aristotle's ethics, arguing that it is not confined to deliberation about means, but that it includes the achievement of the right ...
More
This chapter examines the role of the practical intellect in Aristotle's ethics, arguing that it is not confined to deliberation about means, but that it includes the achievement of the right conception of ends. Close examination of the texts indicates that the achievement of that conception requires rational thought, trained perception of individual cases, and critical examination of generally accepted beliefs, but Aristotle does not spell out a single explicit account. Some texts suggest that the role of the practical intellect is simply to make determinate, via trained moral perception, the indeterminate conception of the life of virtue, others that it has in addition the task of establishing a more determinate conception, specifically the life of theoretical thought, as the highest good.Less
This chapter examines the role of the practical intellect in Aristotle's ethics, arguing that it is not confined to deliberation about means, but that it includes the achievement of the right conception of ends. Close examination of the texts indicates that the achievement of that conception requires rational thought, trained perception of individual cases, and critical examination of generally accepted beliefs, but Aristotle does not spell out a single explicit account. Some texts suggest that the role of the practical intellect is simply to make determinate, via trained moral perception, the indeterminate conception of the life of virtue, others that it has in addition the task of establishing a more determinate conception, specifically the life of theoretical thought, as the highest good.
Martin Laird
- Published in print:
- 2004
- Published Online:
- November 2004
- ISBN:
- 9780199267996
- eISBN:
- 9780191601576
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199267995.003.0003
- Subject:
- Religion, Early Christian Studies
As a backdrop for considering Gregory’s understanding of faith, we discuss how Gregory views the mind itself. How the mind is affected by the passions.Discusses the dispersed mind, the grasping mind, ...
More
As a backdrop for considering Gregory’s understanding of faith, we discuss how Gregory views the mind itself. How the mind is affected by the passions.Discusses the dispersed mind, the grasping mind, the mind and the intelligible, the mind’s ascent, the mind, and grace.Less
As a backdrop for considering Gregory’s understanding of faith, we discuss how Gregory views the mind itself. How the mind is affected by the passions.Discusses the dispersed mind, the grasping mind, the mind and the intelligible, the mind’s ascent, the mind, and grace.
Martin Laird
- Published in print:
- 2004
- Published Online:
- November 2004
- ISBN:
- 9780199267996
- eISBN:
- 9780191601576
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199267995.003.0005
- Subject:
- Religion, Early Christian Studies
In designating a non-discursive faculty of apophatic union, Gregory is doing nothing new. This chapter explores parallels in Middle and Neoplatonism: Celsus, The Chaldaean Oracles, Plotinus. Gregory ...
More
In designating a non-discursive faculty of apophatic union, Gregory is doing nothing new. This chapter explores parallels in Middle and Neoplatonism: Celsus, The Chaldaean Oracles, Plotinus. Gregory ascribes to faith many of the same qualities as others did to faculties of union, yet Gregory differs markedly in the dynamic, exegetical, and sacramental character he accords faith as an apophatic faculty.Less
In designating a non-discursive faculty of apophatic union, Gregory is doing nothing new. This chapter explores parallels in Middle and Neoplatonism: Celsus, The Chaldaean Oracles, Plotinus. Gregory ascribes to faith many of the same qualities as others did to faculties of union, yet Gregory differs markedly in the dynamic, exegetical, and sacramental character he accords faith as an apophatic faculty.
Elizabeth Vlossak
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- January 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199561117
- eISBN:
- 9780191595035
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199561117.003.0008
- Subject:
- History, European Modern History
The image of the Alsatian woman continues to be used as a cultural emblem, yet her historical and political significance, whether real or invented, has largely been forgotten. Moreover, Alsatian ...
More
The image of the Alsatian woman continues to be used as a cultural emblem, yet her historical and political significance, whether real or invented, has largely been forgotten. Moreover, Alsatian memory and the French memory of Alsace have become almost exclusively masculine. This masculinization is especially apparent in the way Alsatians remember the period of Nazi re-annexation. The representatives of Nazi oppression are the tragic Malgré-nous, Alsatians and Mosellans drafted by force into the Wehrmacht, while women's experiences and collective identity fall outside the realm of national memory and commemoration. Marianne or Germania concludes by questioning this continued exclusion. As the book has demonstrated, by taking a gendered approach to Alsace's fascinating history, in which both men and women have played a variety of roles, we gain further insight into the complexities of German and French nation-building, and the processes of national identity formation.Less
The image of the Alsatian woman continues to be used as a cultural emblem, yet her historical and political significance, whether real or invented, has largely been forgotten. Moreover, Alsatian memory and the French memory of Alsace have become almost exclusively masculine. This masculinization is especially apparent in the way Alsatians remember the period of Nazi re-annexation. The representatives of Nazi oppression are the tragic Malgré-nous, Alsatians and Mosellans drafted by force into the Wehrmacht, while women's experiences and collective identity fall outside the realm of national memory and commemoration. Marianne or Germania concludes by questioning this continued exclusion. As the book has demonstrated, by taking a gendered approach to Alsace's fascinating history, in which both men and women have played a variety of roles, we gain further insight into the complexities of German and French nation-building, and the processes of national identity formation.
John Palmer
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- February 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199567904
- eISBN:
- 9780191721717
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199567904.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy
This chapter reassesses Anaxagoras' relation to Parmenides in light of the modal interpretation of Parmenides developed in Chapters 2 to 4. After an initial orientation to the fundamental tenets of ...
More
This chapter reassesses Anaxagoras' relation to Parmenides in light of the modal interpretation of Parmenides developed in Chapters 2 to 4. After an initial orientation to the fundamental tenets of Anaxagoras' physical theory, the chapter critiques the conventional view that Anaxagorean elemental stuffs are intended to be a plurality of Parmenidean entities. It then demonstrates how Anaxagoras' theory of material composition responds effectively instead to certain of Zeno's antinomies. If anything in Anaxagoras' system can be regarded as the analogue of Parmenidean Being, it is Mind or Nous and not his elemental stuffs, which are instead the functional analogues of the principles of Parmenides' cosmology, light and night. Acknowledging the true structural correspondence between their two systems, and abandoning the presumption that Anaxagorean stuffs are meant to be a plurality of Parmenidean beings, opens the way to a better understanding of Anaxagoras' physical theory and its sophisticated compositional hierarchy.Less
This chapter reassesses Anaxagoras' relation to Parmenides in light of the modal interpretation of Parmenides developed in Chapters 2 to 4. After an initial orientation to the fundamental tenets of Anaxagoras' physical theory, the chapter critiques the conventional view that Anaxagorean elemental stuffs are intended to be a plurality of Parmenidean entities. It then demonstrates how Anaxagoras' theory of material composition responds effectively instead to certain of Zeno's antinomies. If anything in Anaxagoras' system can be regarded as the analogue of Parmenidean Being, it is Mind or Nous and not his elemental stuffs, which are instead the functional analogues of the principles of Parmenides' cosmology, light and night. Acknowledging the true structural correspondence between their two systems, and abandoning the presumption that Anaxagorean stuffs are meant to be a plurality of Parmenidean beings, opens the way to a better understanding of Anaxagoras' physical theory and its sophisticated compositional hierarchy.
Talbot Brewer
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- May 2009
- ISBN:
- 9780199557882
- eISBN:
- 9780191720918
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199557882.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
A central thesis of Aristotelian virtue ethics is that practical wisdom cannot be captured in a tractable set of general principles. This raises the question how virtue might be learned and how we ...
More
A central thesis of Aristotelian virtue ethics is that practical wisdom cannot be captured in a tractable set of general principles. This raises the question how virtue might be learned and how we could ever fully articulate or assess our ethical convictions. The task of this chapter is to retrieve a recognizably Aristotelian view that is capable of clarifying these puzzles. On this view, we learn to be good by engaging in relationships sustained by continuously deepening approval by each participant of the other participant's evaluative outlook considered in itself. Healthy parent‐child relationships and good friendships are both relationships of this sort. The seeds of this view can be found in Aristotle's discussion of friendship (philia). This chapter develops a recognizably Aristotelian idea of philia and shows that it both fosters, and requires for its flourishing, an uncodifiable evaluative outlook whose verdicts are affirmable from all relevant social perspectives. This recognizably moral achievement emerges not as a limit on self‐interested pursuits but as a concomitant of a kind of human relationship that is essential to individual flourishing. The connection between virtue and philia lends support to Aristotle's otherwise counterintuitive claim that certain recognizably moral virtues are necessary conditions for happiness.Less
A central thesis of Aristotelian virtue ethics is that practical wisdom cannot be captured in a tractable set of general principles. This raises the question how virtue might be learned and how we could ever fully articulate or assess our ethical convictions. The task of this chapter is to retrieve a recognizably Aristotelian view that is capable of clarifying these puzzles. On this view, we learn to be good by engaging in relationships sustained by continuously deepening approval by each participant of the other participant's evaluative outlook considered in itself. Healthy parent‐child relationships and good friendships are both relationships of this sort. The seeds of this view can be found in Aristotle's discussion of friendship (philia). This chapter develops a recognizably Aristotelian idea of philia and shows that it both fosters, and requires for its flourishing, an uncodifiable evaluative outlook whose verdicts are affirmable from all relevant social perspectives. This recognizably moral achievement emerges not as a limit on self‐interested pursuits but as a concomitant of a kind of human relationship that is essential to individual flourishing. The connection between virtue and philia lends support to Aristotle's otherwise counterintuitive claim that certain recognizably moral virtues are necessary conditions for happiness.
R. J Hankinson
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- May 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199696482
- eISBN:
- 9780191738036
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199696482.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
Plato remarked that Anaxagoras made no use of his nous. But the concept is undeniably important, and equally undeniably complex. Indeed, it is misleading to speak as though there were a single such ...
More
Plato remarked that Anaxagoras made no use of his nous. But the concept is undeniably important, and equally undeniably complex. Indeed, it is misleading to speak as though there were a single such concept at all. Nous in Anaxagoras is not the same as nous in Plato; while Aristotle's various treatments of the subject differ both from those of his predecessors and also, apparently, from one another. It is tempting to conclude that nous is at best a very general umbrella under whose capacious awning a variety of quite distinct ideas may shelter, at worst perhaps that it is simply and irremediably homonymous. Such a view has been adopted by, among others, Jonathan Barnes, the dedicatee of this volume. This chapter, however, shows how some at least of Aristotle's apparently divergent usages of the term in fact conceal an important measure of underlying unity, and in particular to integrate a problematic case in Nicomachean Ethics VI 11 with some of the more central ones.Less
Plato remarked that Anaxagoras made no use of his nous. But the concept is undeniably important, and equally undeniably complex. Indeed, it is misleading to speak as though there were a single such concept at all. Nous in Anaxagoras is not the same as nous in Plato; while Aristotle's various treatments of the subject differ both from those of his predecessors and also, apparently, from one another. It is tempting to conclude that nous is at best a very general umbrella under whose capacious awning a variety of quite distinct ideas may shelter, at worst perhaps that it is simply and irremediably homonymous. Such a view has been adopted by, among others, Jonathan Barnes, the dedicatee of this volume. This chapter, however, shows how some at least of Aristotle's apparently divergent usages of the term in fact conceal an important measure of underlying unity, and in particular to integrate a problematic case in Nicomachean Ethics VI 11 with some of the more central ones.
Wallace Matson
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- January 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199812691
- eISBN:
- 9780199919420
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199812691.003.0016
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
In antiquity conceptions of the soul-what plus a body makes a person- varied greatly. Most included some kind of immortality. Pythagoras initiated the theory of a soul migrating between bodies of ...
More
In antiquity conceptions of the soul-what plus a body makes a person- varied greatly. Most included some kind of immortality. Pythagoras initiated the theory of a soul migrating between bodies of different animals and even vegetables. Anaxagoras made Mind (Nous), the faculty of discerning and imposing order on things, into the cosmic force. However, Aristotle rightly transferred soul from the category of Substance (Thing) to those of Action and Passion (Functions). The soul is the Form of the Body The Atomists postulated special soul atoms, lighter and more mobile than others. At death the combinations disperse. Alone among ancient soul theories, Aristotle's, being based on observations (low beliefs), and getting the ontology right (action-passion), may claim scientific status. It was Plato's, however, which survived into Christian thought, being the principal Greek contribution to Christian theology.Less
In antiquity conceptions of the soul-what plus a body makes a person- varied greatly. Most included some kind of immortality. Pythagoras initiated the theory of a soul migrating between bodies of different animals and even vegetables. Anaxagoras made Mind (Nous), the faculty of discerning and imposing order on things, into the cosmic force. However, Aristotle rightly transferred soul from the category of Substance (Thing) to those of Action and Passion (Functions). The soul is the Form of the Body The Atomists postulated special soul atoms, lighter and more mobile than others. At death the combinations disperse. Alone among ancient soul theories, Aristotle's, being based on observations (low beliefs), and getting the ontology right (action-passion), may claim scientific status. It was Plato's, however, which survived into Christian thought, being the principal Greek contribution to Christian theology.
C. D. C. REEVE
- Published in print:
- 1995
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198235651
- eISBN:
- 9780191679094
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198235651.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
Aristotle's ethical epistemology — his account of ethical knowledge — has two major components. The first explains the nature of our knowledge of ethical universals such as justice, moderation, and ...
More
Aristotle's ethical epistemology — his account of ethical knowledge — has two major components. The first explains the nature of our knowledge of ethical universals such as justice, moderation, and eudaimonia. The second explains how, for example, we are able to use such knowledge in order to determine what justice requires of us in a given particular situation and how to accomplish it. This chapter focuses on the first of these components. It begins by examining Aristotle's conception of unconditional scientific knowledge or epistēmē haplōs. This will allow us to explain why some knowledge of ethical universals holds only hōs epi to polu or for the most part (NE l094b 14–22), and to explore the differences and the no less illuminating similarities that hold between ethical knowledge and scientific-knowledge.Less
Aristotle's ethical epistemology — his account of ethical knowledge — has two major components. The first explains the nature of our knowledge of ethical universals such as justice, moderation, and eudaimonia. The second explains how, for example, we are able to use such knowledge in order to determine what justice requires of us in a given particular situation and how to accomplish it. This chapter focuses on the first of these components. It begins by examining Aristotle's conception of unconditional scientific knowledge or epistēmē haplōs. This will allow us to explain why some knowledge of ethical universals holds only hōs epi to polu or for the most part (NE l094b 14–22), and to explore the differences and the no less illuminating similarities that hold between ethical knowledge and scientific-knowledge.
C. D. C. REEVE
- Published in print:
- 1995
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198235651
- eISBN:
- 9780191679094
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198235651.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
The previous chapters have been largely silent on the philosophical merits of Aristotle's arguments, in the belief that analysis should precede criticism. This concluding chapter discusses how, ...
More
The previous chapters have been largely silent on the philosophical merits of Aristotle's arguments, in the belief that analysis should precede criticism. This concluding chapter discusses how, possessed now of a unified account of the foundations of the Ethics, we ought to assess them and the work that Aristotle has built on them. Has the Ethics anything to teach us? And if so, what are its most important lessons?Less
The previous chapters have been largely silent on the philosophical merits of Aristotle's arguments, in the belief that analysis should precede criticism. This concluding chapter discusses how, possessed now of a unified account of the foundations of the Ethics, we ought to assess them and the work that Aristotle has built on them. Has the Ethics anything to teach us? And if so, what are its most important lessons?
Glanmor Williams
- Published in print:
- 1993
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780192852779
- eISBN:
- 9780191670558
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780192852779.003.0020
- Subject:
- History, British and Irish Early Modern History
Charles was patently different from his father in temperament and in his approach to the task of kingship. James showed more political nous and judgment when dealing with Parliament; he exercised a ...
More
Charles was patently different from his father in temperament and in his approach to the task of kingship. James showed more political nous and judgment when dealing with Parliament; he exercised a more sensitive control of the art. Unlike James though, Charles had moved away from Calvinism and was committed to an Arminian position. Charles’s first demand in Wales for men and money to meet the challenge of the Catholic powers was readily met. Throughout the years of personal rule, it had been essential for Charles to avoid the danger of warfare. At the first sign of any major emergency necessitating the summons of Parliament, much of the latent opposition to him was bound to burst into the open.Less
Charles was patently different from his father in temperament and in his approach to the task of kingship. James showed more political nous and judgment when dealing with Parliament; he exercised a more sensitive control of the art. Unlike James though, Charles had moved away from Calvinism and was committed to an Arminian position. Charles’s first demand in Wales for men and money to meet the challenge of the Catholic powers was readily met. Throughout the years of personal rule, it had been essential for Charles to avoid the danger of warfare. At the first sign of any major emergency necessitating the summons of Parliament, much of the latent opposition to him was bound to burst into the open.
Stephen R.L. Clark
- Published in print:
- 1975
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198245162
- eISBN:
- 9780191680847
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198245162.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy
This chapter explores certain details of the existence and of the theories that have been expounding. It also confirms Aristotle's biological works that must be taken seriously as considered ...
More
This chapter explores certain details of the existence and of the theories that have been expounding. It also confirms Aristotle's biological works that must be taken seriously as considered expressions of his philosophical attitude. It is convenient to study his account of sensory perception first through the eyes of Irving Block. In doing so, the chapter particularly describes the relation between the ‘primary’ and the ‘special’ senses, and the concept of the senses as self-aware, which is used in the earlier biological works. It then addresses the concepts of corrigibility and accuracy, and finally the doctrine of sense or the senses as means. The last point leads on to the ethical mean; self-awareness and accuracy to the discussion of nous. It is concluded that Aristotle's psychological and biological works may legitimately be placed towards the later part of his life – his philosophy turns toward the world; that the relation of primary and special senses, of the critical faculty to the various types of phenomena presented in different sensory dimensions, is an instance of that relation of whole to parts that pervades his work; human senses are variously accurate, detached from immediate pleasure and pain, and grasping of wholes – sight is the paradigm; and the senses are means partly because sense is a mean.Less
This chapter explores certain details of the existence and of the theories that have been expounding. It also confirms Aristotle's biological works that must be taken seriously as considered expressions of his philosophical attitude. It is convenient to study his account of sensory perception first through the eyes of Irving Block. In doing so, the chapter particularly describes the relation between the ‘primary’ and the ‘special’ senses, and the concept of the senses as self-aware, which is used in the earlier biological works. It then addresses the concepts of corrigibility and accuracy, and finally the doctrine of sense or the senses as means. The last point leads on to the ethical mean; self-awareness and accuracy to the discussion of nous. It is concluded that Aristotle's psychological and biological works may legitimately be placed towards the later part of his life – his philosophy turns toward the world; that the relation of primary and special senses, of the critical faculty to the various types of phenomena presented in different sensory dimensions, is an instance of that relation of whole to parts that pervades his work; human senses are variously accurate, detached from immediate pleasure and pain, and grasping of wholes – sight is the paradigm; and the senses are means partly because sense is a mean.
Stephen R.L. Clark
- Published in print:
- 1975
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198245162
- eISBN:
- 9780191680847
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198245162.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy
This chapter attempts to show how Aristotle resolves the tension between the two major views of death: as an intrusion and as a completion. It also hopes to counter the difficulty inherent in any ...
More
This chapter attempts to show how Aristotle resolves the tension between the two major views of death: as an intrusion and as a completion. It also hopes to counter the difficulty inherent in any ethical theory that bases itself on the desire for survival, namely that ethical values may sometimes require the demise. Plato's arguments for immortality lead to Aristotle's belief only in the immortality of nous. One can endure death because one turns to the world and seeks its perfection by living according to the unaging best in them, energetically rather than kinetically. The argument from self-movement, that the soul keeps itself going, and is therefore causa sui and immortal, collapsed when Aristotle decided that literal self-movement was impossible, in that it implied the simultaneous actuality and potentiality of the same entity in the same respect.Less
This chapter attempts to show how Aristotle resolves the tension between the two major views of death: as an intrusion and as a completion. It also hopes to counter the difficulty inherent in any ethical theory that bases itself on the desire for survival, namely that ethical values may sometimes require the demise. Plato's arguments for immortality lead to Aristotle's belief only in the immortality of nous. One can endure death because one turns to the world and seeks its perfection by living according to the unaging best in them, energetically rather than kinetically. The argument from self-movement, that the soul keeps itself going, and is therefore causa sui and immortal, collapsed when Aristotle decided that literal self-movement was impossible, in that it implied the simultaneous actuality and potentiality of the same entity in the same respect.
Stephen R.L. Clark
- Published in print:
- 1975
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198245162
- eISBN:
- 9780191680847
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198245162.003.0012
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy
This chapter makes use of Buddhist and Neo-Confucian parallels: ‘there is a universal mind in which all sages participate, be they from east, south, west or north, past or future’. It hopes that it ...
More
This chapter makes use of Buddhist and Neo-Confucian parallels: ‘there is a universal mind in which all sages participate, be they from east, south, west or north, past or future’. It hopes that it makes this view seem plausible, in both its literal and metaphorical sense. The chapter then follows Alexander of Aphrodisias in identifying poetic nous with the Prime Mover. The intuition of the world as a unitary whole reveals the nature of things and gives only deathlessness. In this, Aristotle is at one with the doctrines of Ch'an Buddhism. Theoria, theo-ria, is the practice of enlightenment.Less
This chapter makes use of Buddhist and Neo-Confucian parallels: ‘there is a universal mind in which all sages participate, be they from east, south, west or north, past or future’. It hopes that it makes this view seem plausible, in both its literal and metaphorical sense. The chapter then follows Alexander of Aphrodisias in identifying poetic nous with the Prime Mover. The intuition of the world as a unitary whole reveals the nature of things and gives only deathlessness. In this, Aristotle is at one with the doctrines of Ch'an Buddhism. Theoria, theo-ria, is the practice of enlightenment.