Paul Horwich
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- February 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199268900
- eISBN:
- 9780191708459
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199268900.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, Philosophy of Language
This chapter defines a paradox, roughly and superficially, as an assembly of apparently reasonable considerations that engender conflicting inclinations about what to believe, and hence a form of ...
More
This chapter defines a paradox, roughly and superficially, as an assembly of apparently reasonable considerations that engender conflicting inclinations about what to believe, and hence a form of cognitive tension. By way of illustration, it examines various philosophical paradoxes — concerning knowledge, motion, freedom, evidence, non-existence, truth, normative facts, and vagueness. In light of these examples, the relative merits of three competing theories of the nature and meta-philosophical import of paradox are discussed: one suggested by Stephen Schiffer, which blames paradoxes on ‘glitch’ concepts; a second diagnosis, due to Wittgenstein, which stresses irrationally stubborn, scientistic over-generalization; and a third — pinned on Quine — for which the causes of paradox are conflicts amongst our fundamental habits of reasoning.Less
This chapter defines a paradox, roughly and superficially, as an assembly of apparently reasonable considerations that engender conflicting inclinations about what to believe, and hence a form of cognitive tension. By way of illustration, it examines various philosophical paradoxes — concerning knowledge, motion, freedom, evidence, non-existence, truth, normative facts, and vagueness. In light of these examples, the relative merits of three competing theories of the nature and meta-philosophical import of paradox are discussed: one suggested by Stephen Schiffer, which blames paradoxes on ‘glitch’ concepts; a second diagnosis, due to Wittgenstein, which stresses irrationally stubborn, scientistic over-generalization; and a third — pinned on Quine — for which the causes of paradox are conflicts amongst our fundamental habits of reasoning.
Paul Horwich
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- April 2005
- ISBN:
- 9780199251261
- eISBN:
- 9780191602252
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199251266.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This essay discusses the programme called ‘therapeutic Bayesianism’ from three abstract points of view: substantial, foundational, and meta-philosophical. It illustrates treatments of the ‘raven’ ...
More
This essay discusses the programme called ‘therapeutic Bayesianism’ from three abstract points of view: substantial, foundational, and meta-philosophical. It illustrates treatments of the ‘raven’ paradox and the puzzle of diverse data, and defends the propriety of certain idealizations. It criticises a meta-philosophical perspective that does not properly distinguish science from the philosophy of science, and overvalues the use of symbolic apparatus.Less
This essay discusses the programme called ‘therapeutic Bayesianism’ from three abstract points of view: substantial, foundational, and meta-philosophical. It illustrates treatments of the ‘raven’ paradox and the puzzle of diverse data, and defends the propriety of certain idealizations. It criticises a meta-philosophical perspective that does not properly distinguish science from the philosophy of science, and overvalues the use of symbolic apparatus.
Penelope Maddy
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- May 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199596188
- eISBN:
- 9780191725395
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199596188.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter lays out the meta-philosophical perspective from which the subsequent inquiry will take place, namely, that of the Second Philosopher. Beginning in her characteristic way, from within ...
More
This chapter lays out the meta-philosophical perspective from which the subsequent inquiry will take place, namely, that of the Second Philosopher. Beginning in her characteristic way, from within the practice, the Second Philosopher surveys a range of set-theoretic examples, historical and contemporary. Though the methods employed differ from her more familiar empirical approach, she judges that they are rational means toward the ends these various set-theoretic practices are out to achieve. Assuming for the moment that the historical and continuing inter-relations of pure mathematics with natural science are enough to warrant the Second Philosopher in regarding set theory as a body of truths, she concludes that its methods are reliable guides to those truths. The challenge, then, is to explain what sort of activity set theory is, what kind of things set are and how we know them, in such a way as to respect those methods. This means avoiding any variety of the familiar Robust Realism, which requires that apparently rational, reliable set-theoretic methods be supplemented or even rejected on the basis of an extra-mathematical metaphysics.Less
This chapter lays out the meta-philosophical perspective from which the subsequent inquiry will take place, namely, that of the Second Philosopher. Beginning in her characteristic way, from within the practice, the Second Philosopher surveys a range of set-theoretic examples, historical and contemporary. Though the methods employed differ from her more familiar empirical approach, she judges that they are rational means toward the ends these various set-theoretic practices are out to achieve. Assuming for the moment that the historical and continuing inter-relations of pure mathematics with natural science are enough to warrant the Second Philosopher in regarding set theory as a body of truths, she concludes that its methods are reliable guides to those truths. The challenge, then, is to explain what sort of activity set theory is, what kind of things set are and how we know them, in such a way as to respect those methods. This means avoiding any variety of the familiar Robust Realism, which requires that apparently rational, reliable set-theoretic methods be supplemented or even rejected on the basis of an extra-mathematical metaphysics.
Jan Westerhoff
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- June 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198847915
- eISBN:
- 9780191882548
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198847915.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
The book is concerned with the existence of the real world, that is, with the existence of a world of objects that exist independent of human interests, concerns, and cognitive activities. The main ...
More
The book is concerned with the existence of the real world, that is, with the existence of a world of objects that exist independent of human interests, concerns, and cognitive activities. The main thesis defended is that we have good reason to deny the existence of such a world. The discussion is concerned with four main facets of assuming a real world: (a) the existence of an external world of physical objects in space and time; (b) the existence of an internal world, comprising various mental states congregated around a self; (c) the existence of an ontological foundation that grounds the existence of all the entities in the world; and (d) the existence of an ultimately true theory that provides a final account of all there is. I argue specifically that: (a) we should reject the postulation of an external world behind our representations; (b) the internal world is not as epistemically transparent as is usually assumed, and there is no substantial self acting as central unifier of our mental lives; (c) there are good reasons for adopting an anti-foundational account of ontological dependence; and (d) ontology, and philosophy more generally, must not be conceived of as providing an ultimately true theory of the world.Less
The book is concerned with the existence of the real world, that is, with the existence of a world of objects that exist independent of human interests, concerns, and cognitive activities. The main thesis defended is that we have good reason to deny the existence of such a world. The discussion is concerned with four main facets of assuming a real world: (a) the existence of an external world of physical objects in space and time; (b) the existence of an internal world, comprising various mental states congregated around a self; (c) the existence of an ontological foundation that grounds the existence of all the entities in the world; and (d) the existence of an ultimately true theory that provides a final account of all there is. I argue specifically that: (a) we should reject the postulation of an external world behind our representations; (b) the internal world is not as epistemically transparent as is usually assumed, and there is no substantial self acting as central unifier of our mental lives; (c) there are good reasons for adopting an anti-foundational account of ontological dependence; and (d) ontology, and philosophy more generally, must not be conceived of as providing an ultimately true theory of the world.
Jacqueline Broad and Karen Detlefsen (eds)
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- December 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198810261
- eISBN:
- 9780191847301
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198810261.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Feminist Philosophy
This book addresses the theme of liberty as it is found in the writing of women philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, or as it is theorized with respect to women and their lives. ...
More
This book addresses the theme of liberty as it is found in the writing of women philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, or as it is theorized with respect to women and their lives. It covers both theoretical and practical philosophy, with chapters on problems in the metaphysics of free will (both human and divine), the liberty (or lack thereof) of women in their moral, personal lives as well as their social-political, public lives, and the interactions between the metaphysical and normative issues. The chapters draw upon writing of both women and men, and notably, upon a wide range of genres, including more standard philosophical treatises as well as polemical texts, poetry, plays, and other forms of fiction. As such, this book alerts the reader to the wide range of conceptions of what counts as a philosophical text in the early modern period. Several chapters also deal with the relation between early modern and contemporary ways of thinking about the theme of women and liberty, thus urging the reader to appreciate the continuing importance of these earlier philosophers in the history of philosophy and of feminism. Ultimately, the chapters in this text show how crucial it is to recover the too-long forgotten views of female and women-friendly male philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, for in the process of recovering these voices, our understanding of philosophy in the early modern period is not only expanded, but also significantly altered towards a more accurate history of our discipline.Less
This book addresses the theme of liberty as it is found in the writing of women philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, or as it is theorized with respect to women and their lives. It covers both theoretical and practical philosophy, with chapters on problems in the metaphysics of free will (both human and divine), the liberty (or lack thereof) of women in their moral, personal lives as well as their social-political, public lives, and the interactions between the metaphysical and normative issues. The chapters draw upon writing of both women and men, and notably, upon a wide range of genres, including more standard philosophical treatises as well as polemical texts, poetry, plays, and other forms of fiction. As such, this book alerts the reader to the wide range of conceptions of what counts as a philosophical text in the early modern period. Several chapters also deal with the relation between early modern and contemporary ways of thinking about the theme of women and liberty, thus urging the reader to appreciate the continuing importance of these earlier philosophers in the history of philosophy and of feminism. Ultimately, the chapters in this text show how crucial it is to recover the too-long forgotten views of female and women-friendly male philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, for in the process of recovering these voices, our understanding of philosophy in the early modern period is not only expanded, but also significantly altered towards a more accurate history of our discipline.
John A. Keller (ed.)
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- January 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198715702
- eISBN:
- 9780191783401
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198715702.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, Philosophy of Religion
In The Philosophy of Philosophy, Timothy Williamson wrote that Peter van Inwagen’s work is among the “liveliest, exactest, and most creative…of the final third of the 20th Century.” This collection ...
More
In The Philosophy of Philosophy, Timothy Williamson wrote that Peter van Inwagen’s work is among the “liveliest, exactest, and most creative…of the final third of the 20th Century.” This collection of original essays addresses some of the most important and interesting themes from van Inwagen’s work, with selected replies by van Inwagen himself. It is no accident that the themes of this volume are also some of the most cutting-edge and important topics in philosophy today. The volume contains rigorous, original, but readable essays, by some of the most prominent living philosophers, on free will, the structure of ordinary objects, time travel, the problem of evil, God and evolution, and the nature of philosophical success. As such, it will be appealing to readers with diverse interests, and will be essential reading for those working on free will, relational vs constituent ontologies, the philosophy of religion, and the philosophy of philosophy.Less
In The Philosophy of Philosophy, Timothy Williamson wrote that Peter van Inwagen’s work is among the “liveliest, exactest, and most creative…of the final third of the 20th Century.” This collection of original essays addresses some of the most important and interesting themes from van Inwagen’s work, with selected replies by van Inwagen himself. It is no accident that the themes of this volume are also some of the most cutting-edge and important topics in philosophy today. The volume contains rigorous, original, but readable essays, by some of the most prominent living philosophers, on free will, the structure of ordinary objects, time travel, the problem of evil, God and evolution, and the nature of philosophical success. As such, it will be appealing to readers with diverse interests, and will be essential reading for those working on free will, relational vs constituent ontologies, the philosophy of religion, and the philosophy of philosophy.
Penelope Maddy
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- January 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780190618698
- eISBN:
- 9780190618728
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190618698.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, General
How do you know the world around you isn’t just an elaborate dream or the creation of an evil neuroscientist? Questions like these lie at the core of venerable philosophical arguments for radical ...
More
How do you know the world around you isn’t just an elaborate dream or the creation of an evil neuroscientist? Questions like these lie at the core of venerable philosophical arguments for radical skepticism: the stark contention that we in fact know nothing at all about the world, that we have no more reason to believe any claim than we have to disbelieve it. Like nonphilosophers in their sober moments, philosophers, too, find this skeptical conclusion preposterous, but they’re faced with those famous arguments: the Dream Argument, the Argument from Illusion, the Infinite Regress of Justification, the more recent Closure Argument. If these can’t be met, they raise a serious challenge not just to philosophers, but to anyone responsible enough to expect her beliefs to square with her evidence. What Do Philosophers Do? takes up the skeptical arguments from this everyday point of view and ultimately concludes that they don’t undermine our ordinary beliefs or our ordinary ways of finding out about the world. In the process, Maddy examines and evaluates a range of philosophical methods—common sense, scientific naturalism, ordinary language, conceptual analysis, therapeutic approaches—as employed by such philosophers as Thomas Reid, G. E. Moore, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and J. L. Austin. The result is a revealing portrait of what philosophers do, and perhaps a quiet suggestion for what they should do, for what they do best.Less
How do you know the world around you isn’t just an elaborate dream or the creation of an evil neuroscientist? Questions like these lie at the core of venerable philosophical arguments for radical skepticism: the stark contention that we in fact know nothing at all about the world, that we have no more reason to believe any claim than we have to disbelieve it. Like nonphilosophers in their sober moments, philosophers, too, find this skeptical conclusion preposterous, but they’re faced with those famous arguments: the Dream Argument, the Argument from Illusion, the Infinite Regress of Justification, the more recent Closure Argument. If these can’t be met, they raise a serious challenge not just to philosophers, but to anyone responsible enough to expect her beliefs to square with her evidence. What Do Philosophers Do? takes up the skeptical arguments from this everyday point of view and ultimately concludes that they don’t undermine our ordinary beliefs or our ordinary ways of finding out about the world. In the process, Maddy examines and evaluates a range of philosophical methods—common sense, scientific naturalism, ordinary language, conceptual analysis, therapeutic approaches—as employed by such philosophers as Thomas Reid, G. E. Moore, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and J. L. Austin. The result is a revealing portrait of what philosophers do, and perhaps a quiet suggestion for what they should do, for what they do best.
Pradeep P. Gokhale
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- January 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780199460632
- eISBN:
- 9780199085507
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199460632.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy
This chapter makes a meta-philosophical claim that Lokāyata, considered as a strong this-worldly rational approach including diverse philosophical trends, can influence one’s approach to Indian ...
More
This chapter makes a meta-philosophical claim that Lokāyata, considered as a strong this-worldly rational approach including diverse philosophical trends, can influence one’s approach to Indian philosophy as a whole. In this light, it takes note of some of the recent Indian philosophers and thinkers who have tried to reassess and reconstruct Indian philosophy by keeping a Lokāyatic or Lokāyata-like approach at the centre. Hence the chapter refers to the following recent thinkers/philosophers: (a) the analytical philosopher Rajendra Prasad, who secularized the theory of the four puruṣārthas, (b) Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya, who turned the traditional hierarchical order among the Indian philosophical schools upside down, (c) S. S. Barlingay, who reinterpreted Advaita–Vedānta, Sāṅkhya, Jainism, and so on, in materialistic terms, and (d) B. R. Ambedkar, who reconstructed Buddhism and synthesized it with Lokāyata. The chapter concludes the work by underlining the need for a Lokāyatic turn in Indian philosophy.Less
This chapter makes a meta-philosophical claim that Lokāyata, considered as a strong this-worldly rational approach including diverse philosophical trends, can influence one’s approach to Indian philosophy as a whole. In this light, it takes note of some of the recent Indian philosophers and thinkers who have tried to reassess and reconstruct Indian philosophy by keeping a Lokāyatic or Lokāyata-like approach at the centre. Hence the chapter refers to the following recent thinkers/philosophers: (a) the analytical philosopher Rajendra Prasad, who secularized the theory of the four puruṣārthas, (b) Debiprasad Chattopadhyaya, who turned the traditional hierarchical order among the Indian philosophical schools upside down, (c) S. S. Barlingay, who reinterpreted Advaita–Vedānta, Sāṅkhya, Jainism, and so on, in materialistic terms, and (d) B. R. Ambedkar, who reconstructed Buddhism and synthesized it with Lokāyata. The chapter concludes the work by underlining the need for a Lokāyatic turn in Indian philosophy.
Paul Horwich
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- December 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780199684939
- eISBN:
- 9780191765230
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199684939.003.0012
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Language
This chapter defines a paradox, roughly and superficially, as an assembly of apparently reasonable considerations that engender conflicting inclinations about what to believe, and hence a form of ...
More
This chapter defines a paradox, roughly and superficially, as an assembly of apparently reasonable considerations that engender conflicting inclinations about what to believe, and hence a form of cognitive tension. By way of illustration, it examines various philosophical paradoxes—concerning knowledge, motion, freedom, evidence, non-existence, truth, normative facts, and vagueness. In light of these examples, the relative merits of three competing theories of the nature and meta-philosophical import of paradox are discussed: one suggested by Schiffer, which blames paradoxes on “glitch” concepts; a second diagnosis, due to Wittgenstein, which stresses irrationally stubborn, scientistic over-generalization; and a third—pinned on Quine—in which the causes of paradox are conflicts amongst our fundamental habits of reasoning.Less
This chapter defines a paradox, roughly and superficially, as an assembly of apparently reasonable considerations that engender conflicting inclinations about what to believe, and hence a form of cognitive tension. By way of illustration, it examines various philosophical paradoxes—concerning knowledge, motion, freedom, evidence, non-existence, truth, normative facts, and vagueness. In light of these examples, the relative merits of three competing theories of the nature and meta-philosophical import of paradox are discussed: one suggested by Schiffer, which blames paradoxes on “glitch” concepts; a second diagnosis, due to Wittgenstein, which stresses irrationally stubborn, scientistic over-generalization; and a third—pinned on Quine—in which the causes of paradox are conflicts amongst our fundamental habits of reasoning.
Jan Westerhoff
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- June 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198847915
- eISBN:
- 9780191882548
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198847915.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
This chapter discusses problems that arise from the assumption that there is a final, ultimately true theory of the world and considers a variety of arguments (connected with the coherence theory of ...
More
This chapter discusses problems that arise from the assumption that there is a final, ultimately true theory of the world and considers a variety of arguments (connected with the coherence theory of truth, semantic contextualism, and the denial of absolutely general quantification) against it. From this it follows that if there cannot be an ultimately true theory then it also cannot be ultimately true that the world has a non-wellfounded structure. This leaves us with a problem, for it appears as if the theory of the non-existence of the real world we defend in the book as a whole cannot be a final theory either. The chapter closes with a discussion of this final problem, together with some reflections on what the implications of the denial of ultimately true theories are for the ontological or philosophical enterprise more generally.Less
This chapter discusses problems that arise from the assumption that there is a final, ultimately true theory of the world and considers a variety of arguments (connected with the coherence theory of truth, semantic contextualism, and the denial of absolutely general quantification) against it. From this it follows that if there cannot be an ultimately true theory then it also cannot be ultimately true that the world has a non-wellfounded structure. This leaves us with a problem, for it appears as if the theory of the non-existence of the real world we defend in the book as a whole cannot be a final theory either. The chapter closes with a discussion of this final problem, together with some reflections on what the implications of the denial of ultimately true theories are for the ontological or philosophical enterprise more generally.
Robert Hanna
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- November 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780198716297
- eISBN:
- 9780191785009
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198716297.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
Chapter 8 presents solutions to all three versions of The Benacerraf Dilemma—namely, The Original Benacerraf Dilemma, The Extended Benacerraf Dilemma, and The Generalized Benacerraf Dilemma—and ...
More
Chapter 8 presents solutions to all three versions of The Benacerraf Dilemma—namely, The Original Benacerraf Dilemma, The Extended Benacerraf Dilemma, and The Generalized Benacerraf Dilemma—and develops a new structuralist account of the nature of mathematics and logic (Kantian Structuralism) alongside a new rational-intuition-based account of the nature of mathematical and logical a priori knowledge (Kantian Intuitionism), comparing and contrasting the two differing accounts with Charles Parsons’s theory. The chapter then moves on to work out a positive or anti-skeptical, innatist, rational-intuition-based solution to The Extended Benacerraf Dilemma. Following this, it then goes on to generalize that solution to The Generalized Benacerraf Dilemma. These solutions and accounts, in turn, presuppose and indirectly vindicate a Kant-inspired rational-intuition-based approach to meta-philosophy.Less
Chapter 8 presents solutions to all three versions of The Benacerraf Dilemma—namely, The Original Benacerraf Dilemma, The Extended Benacerraf Dilemma, and The Generalized Benacerraf Dilemma—and develops a new structuralist account of the nature of mathematics and logic (Kantian Structuralism) alongside a new rational-intuition-based account of the nature of mathematical and logical a priori knowledge (Kantian Intuitionism), comparing and contrasting the two differing accounts with Charles Parsons’s theory. The chapter then moves on to work out a positive or anti-skeptical, innatist, rational-intuition-based solution to The Extended Benacerraf Dilemma. Following this, it then goes on to generalize that solution to The Generalized Benacerraf Dilemma. These solutions and accounts, in turn, presuppose and indirectly vindicate a Kant-inspired rational-intuition-based approach to meta-philosophy.