MATTHEW H. KRAMER
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- January 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780198298991
- eISBN:
- 9780191705205
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198298991.003.0002
- Subject:
- Law, Philosophy of Law
This chapter presents a detailed exposition of the Hohfeldian analysis of legal positions (rights, duties, liberties, no-rights, powers, liabilities, immunities, and disabilities). It then presents ...
More
This chapter presents a detailed exposition of the Hohfeldian analysis of legal positions (rights, duties, liberties, no-rights, powers, liabilities, immunities, and disabilities). It then presents an overview of the debates between the Interest Theory and the Will Theory of legal rights, after which it champions the Interest Theory at length. Among the questions considered is whether a theory of legal rights must rely on certain ethical assumptions or not.Less
This chapter presents a detailed exposition of the Hohfeldian analysis of legal positions (rights, duties, liberties, no-rights, powers, liabilities, immunities, and disabilities). It then presents an overview of the debates between the Interest Theory and the Will Theory of legal rights, after which it champions the Interest Theory at length. Among the questions considered is whether a theory of legal rights must rely on certain ethical assumptions or not.
Matthew H. Kramer
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- January 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780198298991
- eISBN:
- 9780191705205
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198298991.001.0001
- Subject:
- Law, Philosophy of Law
This book engages in essay form in a lively debate over the fundamental characteristics of legal rights. Each chapter considers whether rights essentially protect individuals' interests — as is ...
More
This book engages in essay form in a lively debate over the fundamental characteristics of legal rights. Each chapter considers whether rights essentially protect individuals' interests — as is contended by the Interest Theory of rights — or whether they instead essentially enable individuals to make choices, as the Will Theory of rights maintains. The book addresses many questions, such as the following: What are the necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of a legal right? What is the connection between the existence and the enforcement of a legal right (i.e., between legal rights and legal remedies)? Does the identification of legal rights inevitably involve ethical judgments? To what extent can rights be in conflict? The answers to these and related questions can illuminatingly clarify, though not finally resolve, some of the present-day controversies over abortion, euthanasia, and animal rights.Less
This book engages in essay form in a lively debate over the fundamental characteristics of legal rights. Each chapter considers whether rights essentially protect individuals' interests — as is contended by the Interest Theory of rights — or whether they instead essentially enable individuals to make choices, as the Will Theory of rights maintains. The book addresses many questions, such as the following: What are the necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of a legal right? What is the connection between the existence and the enforcement of a legal right (i.e., between legal rights and legal remedies)? Does the identification of legal rights inevitably involve ethical judgments? To what extent can rights be in conflict? The answers to these and related questions can illuminatingly clarify, though not finally resolve, some of the present-day controversies over abortion, euthanasia, and animal rights.
H. L. A. Hart
- Published in print:
- 1982
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780198254683
- eISBN:
- 9780191681509
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198254683.003.0007
- Subject:
- Law, Philosophy of Law
This chapter gives a compressed account of Bentham's doctrine in a discussion of his theories of legal duty and obligation which he frequently takes as an example of a logical fiction and as a ...
More
This chapter gives a compressed account of Bentham's doctrine in a discussion of his theories of legal duty and obligation which he frequently takes as an example of a logical fiction and as a paradigm to exhibit his special method of analysis. Bentham used this doctrine of logical fictions to dissipate the idea that words like ‘duty’, ‘obligation’, and ‘right’ were names of mysterious entities awaiting men's discovery and incorporation of them in man-made laws or social rules. Words like ‘duty’, ‘obligation’, and ‘right’ did indeed, according to Bentham, require special methods of analysis which he invented for logical fictions as a substitute for the straightforward form of definition by genus and species which he held inapplicable to them.Less
This chapter gives a compressed account of Bentham's doctrine in a discussion of his theories of legal duty and obligation which he frequently takes as an example of a logical fiction and as a paradigm to exhibit his special method of analysis. Bentham used this doctrine of logical fictions to dissipate the idea that words like ‘duty’, ‘obligation’, and ‘right’ were names of mysterious entities awaiting men's discovery and incorporation of them in man-made laws or social rules. Words like ‘duty’, ‘obligation’, and ‘right’ did indeed, according to Bentham, require special methods of analysis which he invented for logical fictions as a substitute for the straightforward form of definition by genus and species which he held inapplicable to them.
J. E. Parkinson
- Published in print:
- 1995
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780198259893
- eISBN:
- 9780191682018
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198259893.003.0019
- Subject:
- Law, Company and Commercial Law
This chapter explores the role of law in overcoming the problem through the imposition of legal duties which limit the purposes for which managerial discretion may legitimately be exercised. The ...
More
This chapter explores the role of law in overcoming the problem through the imposition of legal duties which limit the purposes for which managerial discretion may legitimately be exercised. The relevant duty is the duty to act bona fide for the benefit of the company. The chapter also concentrates on the role and effectiveness of rule-based standards, and judicial monitoring of compliance with them, as a technique for shaping management behaviour. It also examines the way in which the law has defined the ends for which the directors must exercise their powers. It then addresses the effectiveness of the law as a control technique in holding directors to the ends so specified. In general, the duty to act in the interests of the company (i.e. the shareholders) imposes only a weak control on managerial discretion, since any plausible assertion that a course of action is designed to increase the company's financial well-being will be enough to protect it from attack. It follows that the duty cannot be expected to play a major part in controlling managerialist tendencies.Less
This chapter explores the role of law in overcoming the problem through the imposition of legal duties which limit the purposes for which managerial discretion may legitimately be exercised. The relevant duty is the duty to act bona fide for the benefit of the company. The chapter also concentrates on the role and effectiveness of rule-based standards, and judicial monitoring of compliance with them, as a technique for shaping management behaviour. It also examines the way in which the law has defined the ends for which the directors must exercise their powers. It then addresses the effectiveness of the law as a control technique in holding directors to the ends so specified. In general, the duty to act in the interests of the company (i.e. the shareholders) imposes only a weak control on managerial discretion, since any plausible assertion that a course of action is designed to increase the company's financial well-being will be enough to protect it from attack. It follows that the duty cannot be expected to play a major part in controlling managerialist tendencies.
Victor Tadros
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- July 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780190865269
- eISBN:
- 9780190865290
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780190865269.003.0009
- Subject:
- Law, Criminal Law and Criminology
This chapter argues that civil wrongs are central to remedies. It shows that private law remedies are primarily responsive to wrongs. Furthermore, the stringency of secondary or remedial duties ...
More
This chapter argues that civil wrongs are central to remedies. It shows that private law remedies are primarily responsive to wrongs. Furthermore, the stringency of secondary or remedial duties reflects the special moral significance of wrongs as such. This chapter attributes the tendency to discount the normative relationship between wrongs and remedies to lack of clarity on that between primary and secondary moral and legal duties. Here, the justification for secondary legal duties becomes an extension of that for secondary moral duties. This implies that the way forward lies in the clarification of the normative significance of the deontic structure of private law and, in turn, the associated moral aims of private law.Less
This chapter argues that civil wrongs are central to remedies. It shows that private law remedies are primarily responsive to wrongs. Furthermore, the stringency of secondary or remedial duties reflects the special moral significance of wrongs as such. This chapter attributes the tendency to discount the normative relationship between wrongs and remedies to lack of clarity on that between primary and secondary moral and legal duties. Here, the justification for secondary legal duties becomes an extension of that for secondary moral duties. This implies that the way forward lies in the clarification of the normative significance of the deontic structure of private law and, in turn, the associated moral aims of private law.
N.E. Simmonds
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199552191
- eISBN:
- 9780191701597
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199552191.003.0004
- Subject:
- Law, Philosophy of Law
The philosophy of law has tended to concern itself with the structural types of questions, such as whether the normativity of morality can be reduced to the normativity of rational self-interest. ...
More
The philosophy of law has tended to concern itself with the structural types of questions, such as whether the normativity of morality can be reduced to the normativity of rational self-interest. Legal positivists, such as John Austin, asserted a clear separation between law and morality, such as by equating the existence of legal duties with the likelihood of the duty-bearer suffering a sanction. However, his critics noted that one might have a legal duty even though one is in fact unlikely to suffer any sanction, and they took the failure of such reductive analyses to indicate a more general failure of legal positivism. Hans Kelsen originally sought to defend legal positivism, but ultimately concluded that positivism could sustain the normative character of law, though only by treating legal discourse as grounded in a basic assumption of law's bindingness, what he called the Grundnorm. HLA Hart rejected Kelsen's theory of the Grundnorm, but agreed that while reductivism was certainly to be rejected for its failure to capture the normative character of law, the rejection of reductivism should not lead to a rejection of legal positivism, since the prescriptive action-guiding character of propositions of law can still be preserved without grounding law in morality. However, the author argues that Hart's theory, though not to be underestimated in power and subtlety, should nevertheless be ultimately rejected for being a mere tautology, since by effectively defining legal validity in terms of derivability from the rule of recognition, it, of course, follows that the concept cannot be applied to the Rule itself.Less
The philosophy of law has tended to concern itself with the structural types of questions, such as whether the normativity of morality can be reduced to the normativity of rational self-interest. Legal positivists, such as John Austin, asserted a clear separation between law and morality, such as by equating the existence of legal duties with the likelihood of the duty-bearer suffering a sanction. However, his critics noted that one might have a legal duty even though one is in fact unlikely to suffer any sanction, and they took the failure of such reductive analyses to indicate a more general failure of legal positivism. Hans Kelsen originally sought to defend legal positivism, but ultimately concluded that positivism could sustain the normative character of law, though only by treating legal discourse as grounded in a basic assumption of law's bindingness, what he called the Grundnorm. HLA Hart rejected Kelsen's theory of the Grundnorm, but agreed that while reductivism was certainly to be rejected for its failure to capture the normative character of law, the rejection of reductivism should not lead to a rejection of legal positivism, since the prescriptive action-guiding character of propositions of law can still be preserved without grounding law in morality. However, the author argues that Hart's theory, though not to be underestimated in power and subtlety, should nevertheless be ultimately rejected for being a mere tautology, since by effectively defining legal validity in terms of derivability from the rule of recognition, it, of course, follows that the concept cannot be applied to the Rule itself.
Jeroen Kortmann
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199280056
- eISBN:
- 9780191700101
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199280056.001.0001
- Subject:
- Law, Law of Obligations
This book examines two problems in private law that are posed by the ‘good Samaritan’: First, do we have a legal duty to give aid to our fellow human beings? In particular: can we be held liable for ...
More
This book examines two problems in private law that are posed by the ‘good Samaritan’: First, do we have a legal duty to give aid to our fellow human beings? In particular: can we be held liable for damages if we fail to do so? Second, if we do come to the rescue, will we have any claim for the expenses that we incurred, or for a reward? This book examines and compares the responses of the Roman, French, German, and English legal systems to these problems, providing a treatment of English law in relation to ‘liability for nonfeasance’ (or ‘liability for omissions’) and negotiorum gestio (or ‘the doctrine of necessity’). In Part I, the book examines English law, which draws a distinction between action and inaction or ‘feasance’ and ‘nonfeasance’. In general, one is not held liable for failing to act. It explores the theoretical justifications for drawing this distinction and the different approaches taken in France and Germany, concluding that the English rule of no liability for nonfeasance requires reconsideration. In Part II the English approach to the problem of reimbursement or reward is examined, detailing its profound differences from the Continental European approach. In principle, English law does not grant the necessitous intervener a claim against the beneficiary of his intervention. The book examines the theoretical justifications for assuming this position and again concludes that the law deserves reconsideration. Finally, the book concludes by demonstrating close interconnections between the two traditionally independent issues.Less
This book examines two problems in private law that are posed by the ‘good Samaritan’: First, do we have a legal duty to give aid to our fellow human beings? In particular: can we be held liable for damages if we fail to do so? Second, if we do come to the rescue, will we have any claim for the expenses that we incurred, or for a reward? This book examines and compares the responses of the Roman, French, German, and English legal systems to these problems, providing a treatment of English law in relation to ‘liability for nonfeasance’ (or ‘liability for omissions’) and negotiorum gestio (or ‘the doctrine of necessity’). In Part I, the book examines English law, which draws a distinction between action and inaction or ‘feasance’ and ‘nonfeasance’. In general, one is not held liable for failing to act. It explores the theoretical justifications for drawing this distinction and the different approaches taken in France and Germany, concluding that the English rule of no liability for nonfeasance requires reconsideration. In Part II the English approach to the problem of reimbursement or reward is examined, detailing its profound differences from the Continental European approach. In principle, English law does not grant the necessitous intervener a claim against the beneficiary of his intervention. The book examines the theoretical justifications for assuming this position and again concludes that the law deserves reconsideration. Finally, the book concludes by demonstrating close interconnections between the two traditionally independent issues.
Jeroen Kortmann
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199280056
- eISBN:
- 9780191700101
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199280056.003.0001
- Subject:
- Law, Law of Obligations
This book commences with the biblical parable of the good Samaritan. This parable raises two private law issues: firstly, whether those who are in the position of the priest and the Levite have a ...
More
This book commences with the biblical parable of the good Samaritan. This parable raises two private law issues: firstly, whether those who are in the position of the priest and the Levite have a legal duty to aid the wounded man and, secondly, whether those who do intervene have in law a claim against the beneficiary of their intervention. Both issues are addressed separately. Part I is concerned with the former issue. In Part II, the second issue is addressed. Again, it emerges that the approach taken by the English courts is fundamentally different from the position in civilian jurisdictions. Where English law in principle denies the good Samaritan a claim, French and German law contain a general rule that does grant the intervener a right to be reimbursed for expenses incurred and to be compensated for loss suffered.Less
This book commences with the biblical parable of the good Samaritan. This parable raises two private law issues: firstly, whether those who are in the position of the priest and the Levite have a legal duty to aid the wounded man and, secondly, whether those who do intervene have in law a claim against the beneficiary of their intervention. Both issues are addressed separately. Part I is concerned with the former issue. In Part II, the second issue is addressed. Again, it emerges that the approach taken by the English courts is fundamentally different from the position in civilian jurisdictions. Where English law in principle denies the good Samaritan a claim, French and German law contain a general rule that does grant the intervener a right to be reimbursed for expenses incurred and to be compensated for loss suffered.
Richard Wilmot-Smith QC
- Published in print:
- 2021
- Published Online:
- July 2021
- ISBN:
- 9780198832805
- eISBN:
- 9780191926587
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198832805.003.0006
- Subject:
- Law, Company and Commercial Law, Employment Law
This chapter analyses the law of tort that relates to damage and addresses the question of whether the damage is actionable if it is caused by someone’s negligence. It explains how the law of tort is ...
More
This chapter analyses the law of tort that relates to damage and addresses the question of whether the damage is actionable if it is caused by someone’s negligence. It explains how the law of tort is not to be understood only by the creation of a legal duty rather is dependent upon damage. It also notes the recovery in tort if someone has suffered damage, which is in contra-distinction to the law of contract. This chapter looks at damage and its categorization, focusing on the tort of negligence in relation to defective structures that has two separate species. It describes the first species that permits recovery for direct costs or losses that suffered as a result of a negligent act or omission, while the second species relates to all losses.Less
This chapter analyses the law of tort that relates to damage and addresses the question of whether the damage is actionable if it is caused by someone’s negligence. It explains how the law of tort is not to be understood only by the creation of a legal duty rather is dependent upon damage. It also notes the recovery in tort if someone has suffered damage, which is in contra-distinction to the law of contract. This chapter looks at damage and its categorization, focusing on the tort of negligence in relation to defective structures that has two separate species. It describes the first species that permits recovery for direct costs or losses that suffered as a result of a negligent act or omission, while the second species relates to all losses.
Sandy Summers and Harry Jacobs Summers
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- November 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199337064
- eISBN:
- 9780190221423
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199337064.003.0004
- Subject:
- Public Health and Epidemiology, Public Health
Much of the media presents nurses as the faceless crew of a healthcare ship captained by charismatic physicians. But nursing is an autonomous profession. Nurses train and manage themselves. They have ...
More
Much of the media presents nurses as the faceless crew of a healthcare ship captained by charismatic physicians. But nursing is an autonomous profession. Nurses train and manage themselves. They have independent legal duties to patients and a unique scope of practice, including special expertise in such areas as pain management. Hundreds of thousands have graduate degrees in nursing. Occasionally media products have given some sense of nursing autonomy, including a few news media items and fictional portrayals, such as Call the Midwife. But the most influential entertainment media presents nurses as physician handmaidens. Major Hollywood hospital shows have done so regularly, including Grey’s Anatomy, House, and The Mindy Project. The paradigmatic nurse-physician interaction is a physician “order” followed by a meek nurse’s “Yes, doctor!” Although recent US nurse-focused shows have shown nurses pushing back against poor physician care, each has at times wrongly suggested that nurses report to physicians.Less
Much of the media presents nurses as the faceless crew of a healthcare ship captained by charismatic physicians. But nursing is an autonomous profession. Nurses train and manage themselves. They have independent legal duties to patients and a unique scope of practice, including special expertise in such areas as pain management. Hundreds of thousands have graduate degrees in nursing. Occasionally media products have given some sense of nursing autonomy, including a few news media items and fictional portrayals, such as Call the Midwife. But the most influential entertainment media presents nurses as physician handmaidens. Major Hollywood hospital shows have done so regularly, including Grey’s Anatomy, House, and The Mindy Project. The paradigmatic nurse-physician interaction is a physician “order” followed by a meek nurse’s “Yes, doctor!” Although recent US nurse-focused shows have shown nurses pushing back against poor physician care, each has at times wrongly suggested that nurses report to physicians.