Stanley E. Hoffer
- Published in print:
- 2007
- Published Online:
- September 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780199203956
- eISBN:
- 9780191708244
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199203956.003.0004
- Subject:
- Classical Studies, Literary Studies: Classical, Early, and Medieval
This chapter examines the Ciceronian letter collection, a rare and precious example of an informal and almost spontaneous writing style among the Roman elite, and how much Cicero's epistolary style ...
More
This chapter examines the Ciceronian letter collection, a rare and precious example of an informal and almost spontaneous writing style among the Roman elite, and how much Cicero's epistolary style reflects casual spoken Latin among the elite. In some of Cicero's letters to Atticus, his thoughts and manner of expression from day to day, even hour to hour, can sometimes be tracked. The degree to which the collection is still only a formalized literary representation of actual conversation is discussed by focusing on a prominent feature of Cicero's letters — the use of repeated allusive expressions — paying special attention to expressions that refer to resentment and suppressed indignation (often involving the word stomachus). Such features are analysed as their tendency to cluster together, their tendency to be used at rhetorical turning-points and in connection with epistolary content and style, and, most notably, their tendency to have loaded political significance in expressing resentment at the despotism of Julius Caesar and other dynasts. The chapter aims to show how one can simultaneously analyse Cicero's intimate letters both as rare windows into casual Latin conversation and as masterpieces of literary construction in the epistolary genre.Less
This chapter examines the Ciceronian letter collection, a rare and precious example of an informal and almost spontaneous writing style among the Roman elite, and how much Cicero's epistolary style reflects casual spoken Latin among the elite. In some of Cicero's letters to Atticus, his thoughts and manner of expression from day to day, even hour to hour, can sometimes be tracked. The degree to which the collection is still only a formalized literary representation of actual conversation is discussed by focusing on a prominent feature of Cicero's letters — the use of repeated allusive expressions — paying special attention to expressions that refer to resentment and suppressed indignation (often involving the word stomachus). Such features are analysed as their tendency to cluster together, their tendency to be used at rhetorical turning-points and in connection with epistolary content and style, and, most notably, their tendency to have loaded political significance in expressing resentment at the despotism of Julius Caesar and other dynasts. The chapter aims to show how one can simultaneously analyse Cicero's intimate letters both as rare windows into casual Latin conversation and as masterpieces of literary construction in the epistolary genre.
Robert A. Kaster
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- September 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780195140781
- eISBN:
- 9780199789283
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195140781.003.0005
- Subject:
- Classical Studies, European History: BCE to 500CE
This chapter investigates the various scripts of invidia, the Latin term from which English “envy” is ultimately derived, though the Latin term is of much wider application. A system or “taxonomy” of ...
More
This chapter investigates the various scripts of invidia, the Latin term from which English “envy” is ultimately derived, though the Latin term is of much wider application. A system or “taxonomy” of scripts is described, and it is shown how the emotion — a form of distress felt when you see another person enjoy some sort of good — ranges from sheer malice to righteous indignation depending on whether or not the person experiencing the emotion is applying some principle of right or fairness. The chapter then shows how the different forms of the script commonly interacted in Roman social life.Less
This chapter investigates the various scripts of invidia, the Latin term from which English “envy” is ultimately derived, though the Latin term is of much wider application. A system or “taxonomy” of scripts is described, and it is shown how the emotion — a form of distress felt when you see another person enjoy some sort of good — ranges from sheer malice to righteous indignation depending on whether or not the person experiencing the emotion is applying some principle of right or fairness. The chapter then shows how the different forms of the script commonly interacted in Roman social life.
Ishtiyaque Haji
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199899203
- eISBN:
- 9780199949885
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199899203.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
It is argued in this chapter that various moral sentiments, such as forgiveness, guilt, and indignation are essentially associated with objective reasons. It is also proposed that the truth of ...
More
It is argued in this chapter that various moral sentiments, such as forgiveness, guilt, and indignation are essentially associated with objective reasons. It is also proposed that the truth of certain judgments concerning happiness as well as the truth of a number of virtue judgments is also essentially linked to our having objective reasons, and, thus, to our having alternatives.Less
It is argued in this chapter that various moral sentiments, such as forgiveness, guilt, and indignation are essentially associated with objective reasons. It is also proposed that the truth of certain judgments concerning happiness as well as the truth of a number of virtue judgments is also essentially linked to our having objective reasons, and, thus, to our having alternatives.
Patrick Coleman
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- January 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199589340
- eISBN:
- 9780191723322
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199589340.003.0004
- Subject:
- Literature, European Literature, 18th-century Literature
This chapter analyzes Rousseau's evolving relationship with his public by examining the distinctions he draws between good and bad anger, between righteous indignation and self-centered resentment. ...
More
This chapter analyzes Rousseau's evolving relationship with his public by examining the distinctions he draws between good and bad anger, between righteous indignation and self-centered resentment. The different ways anger is discussed and displayed in the two Discours, in the Lettre à d'Alembert, in Julie, ou la nouvelle Héloïse, and in Émile, serve to legitimize the low-born author's critique of social conventions and to provoke his readers to action. Yet, they also illustrate Rousseau's belief that a Senecan transcendence of emotion is a key both to social harmony and to the inner equilibrium of the self, and equanimity no less than a Juvenalian capacity for anger is set up as evidence of the author's claim to cultural authority. The tension between these two attitudes is shown to be a primary source of dynamism in Rousseau's work.Less
This chapter analyzes Rousseau's evolving relationship with his public by examining the distinctions he draws between good and bad anger, between righteous indignation and self-centered resentment. The different ways anger is discussed and displayed in the two Discours, in the Lettre à d'Alembert, in Julie, ou la nouvelle Héloïse, and in Émile, serve to legitimize the low-born author's critique of social conventions and to provoke his readers to action. Yet, they also illustrate Rousseau's belief that a Senecan transcendence of emotion is a key both to social harmony and to the inner equilibrium of the self, and equanimity no less than a Juvenalian capacity for anger is set up as evidence of the author's claim to cultural authority. The tension between these two attitudes is shown to be a primary source of dynamism in Rousseau's work.
Timothy Gorringe
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198752462
- eISBN:
- 9780191695117
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198752462.003.0003
- Subject:
- Religion, Theology, History of Christianity
When Barth had already started with his rewriting of the Romans, he was offered the possibility of receiving a Chair position at Göttingen in January 1921 that was confirmed in May of that year. ...
More
When Barth had already started with his rewriting of the Romans, he was offered the possibility of receiving a Chair position at Göttingen in January 1921 that was confirmed in May of that year. After the demise of the Weimar Republic, Barth was then expelled from Germany. General Ludendorff — who initiated 1918's spring offensive — informed the Kaiser that suing for peace would be necessary by the end of September in that year. Although there were attempts at maintaining a liberalized monarchy, various events kept this from being achieved. As we look into the different significant impacts brought about by the war, this chapter attempts to illustrate how Barth shared a German indignation during the Ruhr occupation, how Barth had made various observations regarding the German academic life during the period, and how Barth's theology is located against not only the intellectual and cultural background, but also against political events.Less
When Barth had already started with his rewriting of the Romans, he was offered the possibility of receiving a Chair position at Göttingen in January 1921 that was confirmed in May of that year. After the demise of the Weimar Republic, Barth was then expelled from Germany. General Ludendorff — who initiated 1918's spring offensive — informed the Kaiser that suing for peace would be necessary by the end of September in that year. Although there were attempts at maintaining a liberalized monarchy, various events kept this from being achieved. As we look into the different significant impacts brought about by the war, this chapter attempts to illustrate how Barth shared a German indignation during the Ruhr occupation, how Barth had made various observations regarding the German academic life during the period, and how Barth's theology is located against not only the intellectual and cultural background, but also against political events.
Dennis Krebs
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- September 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199778232
- eISBN:
- 9780199897261
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199778232.001.0001
- Subject:
- Psychology, Evolutionary Psychology, Social Psychology
This book updates Darwin’s early account of the evolution of morality in light of contemporary theory and research from a wide array of academic areas. The evidence supports two main propositions. ...
More
This book updates Darwin’s early account of the evolution of morality in light of contemporary theory and research from a wide array of academic areas. The evidence supports two main propositions. First, a capacity for morality evolved in the human species because it helped early humans survive, reproduce, and propagate their genes. Second, traditional psychological accounts of morality can be improved by recognizing that processes such as those that regulate social learning, moral reasoning, empathy, perspective-taking, and conscience, are products of evolution. To account for the sources of morality featured in psychological theories, we must understand the functions that they evolved to serve. Dispositions to exert self-control, to defer to authority, to obey rules that uphold the social order, to punish transgressors, and to behave in altruistic and cooperative ways evolved because they helped early humans advance their biological interests and reap the benefits of group living. Old brain mechanisms that humans share with other primates engender primitive aspects of a sense of morality, such as feelings of moral obligation, sympathy, gratitude, guilt, forgiveness, and righteous indignation. Although new brain mechanisms endow humans with higher-order cognitive abilities that enable them to override primitive impulses, people are only provisionally rational, and often use mental shortcuts that are susceptible to a variety of cognitive biases to make moral decisions in their everyday lives. People are naturally-disposed to be as moral as they have to be to advance their interests, and a little bit more.Less
This book updates Darwin’s early account of the evolution of morality in light of contemporary theory and research from a wide array of academic areas. The evidence supports two main propositions. First, a capacity for morality evolved in the human species because it helped early humans survive, reproduce, and propagate their genes. Second, traditional psychological accounts of morality can be improved by recognizing that processes such as those that regulate social learning, moral reasoning, empathy, perspective-taking, and conscience, are products of evolution. To account for the sources of morality featured in psychological theories, we must understand the functions that they evolved to serve. Dispositions to exert self-control, to defer to authority, to obey rules that uphold the social order, to punish transgressors, and to behave in altruistic and cooperative ways evolved because they helped early humans advance their biological interests and reap the benefits of group living. Old brain mechanisms that humans share with other primates engender primitive aspects of a sense of morality, such as feelings of moral obligation, sympathy, gratitude, guilt, forgiveness, and righteous indignation. Although new brain mechanisms endow humans with higher-order cognitive abilities that enable them to override primitive impulses, people are only provisionally rational, and often use mental shortcuts that are susceptible to a variety of cognitive biases to make moral decisions in their everyday lives. People are naturally-disposed to be as moral as they have to be to advance their interests, and a little bit more.
Adrienne M. Martin
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- October 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780691151526
- eISBN:
- 9781400848706
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691151526.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This chapter argues that hope plays a crucial role in our standard ways of relating to each other “interpersonally” (and to ourselves intrapersonally). One way that we relate to each other ...
More
This chapter argues that hope plays a crucial role in our standard ways of relating to each other “interpersonally” (and to ourselves intrapersonally). One way that we relate to each other interpersonally—or from the “participant stance”—is to hold each other responsible. This mode of interaction is best construed as a “normative expectation.” This chapter argues that to normatively expect someone to comply with a requirement is to be prepared to justify a narrow set of “reactive” feelings: resentment, indignation, and guilt. Normative expectation and these reactive feelings are at the heart of relating to people as rational agents by holding them responsible.Less
This chapter argues that hope plays a crucial role in our standard ways of relating to each other “interpersonally” (and to ourselves intrapersonally). One way that we relate to each other interpersonally—or from the “participant stance”—is to hold each other responsible. This mode of interaction is best construed as a “normative expectation.” This chapter argues that to normatively expect someone to comply with a requirement is to be prepared to justify a narrow set of “reactive” feelings: resentment, indignation, and guilt. Normative expectation and these reactive feelings are at the heart of relating to people as rational agents by holding them responsible.
Javier Krauel
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- May 2014
- ISBN:
- 9781846319761
- eISBN:
- 9781781380963
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Liverpool University Press
- DOI:
- 10.5949/liverpool/9781846319761.003.0005
- Subject:
- History, Cultural History
This chapter examines another fin-de-siècle canonical essay about the symbolic constitution of the Spanish people, Ramiro de Maeztu’s Hacia otra España (1899). The chapter draws on philosophical ...
More
This chapter examines another fin-de-siècle canonical essay about the symbolic constitution of the Spanish people, Ramiro de Maeztu’s Hacia otra España (1899). The chapter draws on philosophical accounts of the emotion of indignation, using classical and contemporary sources (Aristotle, Antonio Valdecantos, Robert Solomon, Victoria Camps), to distinguish between anger—for which Maeztu was famous—and indignation. Bringing Nietzsche’s reflections on the role of historical knowledge together with these accounts of emotion, the chapter argues that Maeztu is a critical historian who views the recent imperial past with indignation and who seeks to replace the old-fashioned, pre-industrial glories of the Spanish empire in America with the industrial bourgeoisie’s the conquest and colonization (the capitalist modernization) of the Castilian plains. This approach to Maeztu reveals the weak normative commitments of his national project, which relied heavily on an emotional critique of empire, something that is evident in his later work, especially his deeply traditionalist, utopian essay Defensa de la Hispanidad (1934).Less
This chapter examines another fin-de-siècle canonical essay about the symbolic constitution of the Spanish people, Ramiro de Maeztu’s Hacia otra España (1899). The chapter draws on philosophical accounts of the emotion of indignation, using classical and contemporary sources (Aristotle, Antonio Valdecantos, Robert Solomon, Victoria Camps), to distinguish between anger—for which Maeztu was famous—and indignation. Bringing Nietzsche’s reflections on the role of historical knowledge together with these accounts of emotion, the chapter argues that Maeztu is a critical historian who views the recent imperial past with indignation and who seeks to replace the old-fashioned, pre-industrial glories of the Spanish empire in America with the industrial bourgeoisie’s the conquest and colonization (the capitalist modernization) of the Castilian plains. This approach to Maeztu reveals the weak normative commitments of his national project, which relied heavily on an emotional critique of empire, something that is evident in his later work, especially his deeply traditionalist, utopian essay Defensa de la Hispanidad (1934).
David Brin
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- January 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199738571
- eISBN:
- 9780199918669
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199738571.003.0062
- Subject:
- Psychology, Social Psychology
The word “addiction” appears to limit our perception of a much wider realm—general behavioral reinforcement within the human brain. If neurochemical processes reinforce “good” habits such as love, ...
More
The word “addiction” appears to limit our perception of a much wider realm—general behavioral reinforcement within the human brain. If neurochemical processes reinforce “good” habits such as love, loyalty, and joy in music or skill, then addiction should be studied in a larger context of both harmful and wholesome reinforcement triggers, their commonalities and differences. Self-righteousness and indignation may sometimes become pernicious addictive habits, arising as much from chemical need as from valid concerns about unfair actions. Among other outcomes, this may cause pathologically altruistic behavior. Indignation addiction may underpin the obstinate behavior of those on both the far left and far right of the political spectrum. Moderate-progressives who seek problem-solving pragmatism may get a boost if it were openly demonstrated that the self-righteous mental state is reinforced chemically by hijacking internal addiction mechanisms.Less
The word “addiction” appears to limit our perception of a much wider realm—general behavioral reinforcement within the human brain. If neurochemical processes reinforce “good” habits such as love, loyalty, and joy in music or skill, then addiction should be studied in a larger context of both harmful and wholesome reinforcement triggers, their commonalities and differences. Self-righteousness and indignation may sometimes become pernicious addictive habits, arising as much from chemical need as from valid concerns about unfair actions. Among other outcomes, this may cause pathologically altruistic behavior. Indignation addiction may underpin the obstinate behavior of those on both the far left and far right of the political spectrum. Moderate-progressives who seek problem-solving pragmatism may get a boost if it were openly demonstrated that the self-righteous mental state is reinforced chemically by hijacking internal addiction mechanisms.
Glen Pettigrove
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- January 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199646555
- eISBN:
- 9780191741975
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199646555.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
Who may forgive? Most philosophical accounts assume that only the victim of a wrongdoing has the standing to forgive. In many cases, this answer to the question is asserted without even an attempt at ...
More
Who may forgive? Most philosophical accounts assume that only the victim of a wrongdoing has the standing to forgive. In many cases, this answer to the question is asserted without even an attempt at offering a supporting argument. However, when reasons are offered, they tend to take one of four forms: the debt-cancelling argument, the emotion-based argument, the relation-based argument, or the normative difference argument. In this chapter, these four arguments are shown to be inadequate. In addition, a case is made for expanding the class of those with the standing to forgive to include second and third parties.Less
Who may forgive? Most philosophical accounts assume that only the victim of a wrongdoing has the standing to forgive. In many cases, this answer to the question is asserted without even an attempt at offering a supporting argument. However, when reasons are offered, they tend to take one of four forms: the debt-cancelling argument, the emotion-based argument, the relation-based argument, or the normative difference argument. In this chapter, these four arguments are shown to be inadequate. In addition, a case is made for expanding the class of those with the standing to forgive to include second and third parties.
Dennis L. Krebs
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- September 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199778232
- eISBN:
- 9780199897261
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199778232.003.0023
- Subject:
- Psychology, Evolutionary Psychology, Social Psychology
This chapter discusses theory and research on mental mechanisms that mediate primitive prosocial behaviors, including the neuro-hormonal mechanisms that mediate impulsive helping behaviors and those ...
More
This chapter discusses theory and research on mental mechanisms that mediate primitive prosocial behaviors, including the neuro-hormonal mechanisms that mediate impulsive helping behaviors and those that give rise to such emotional reactions as fear, admiration, sympathy, gratitude, pride, guilt, shame, indignation, vindictiveness, and forgiveness. Evidence that empathy and sympathy dispose people to want to help others as an end in itself is reviewed. It is argued that the emotions that mediate prosocial behaviors evolved because they disposed people to forgo immediate benefits and to suffer immediate costs in order to maximize long-term gains. Emotionally-mediated dispositions to make commitments and to invest in members of their groups evolved because the fitness of those making the investments was linked to the fitness of those in whom they invested, and because the long-term benefits of credibility and a reputation for trustworthiness outweighed the short-term costs of keeping promises and carrying out threats.Less
This chapter discusses theory and research on mental mechanisms that mediate primitive prosocial behaviors, including the neuro-hormonal mechanisms that mediate impulsive helping behaviors and those that give rise to such emotional reactions as fear, admiration, sympathy, gratitude, pride, guilt, shame, indignation, vindictiveness, and forgiveness. Evidence that empathy and sympathy dispose people to want to help others as an end in itself is reviewed. It is argued that the emotions that mediate prosocial behaviors evolved because they disposed people to forgo immediate benefits and to suffer immediate costs in order to maximize long-term gains. Emotionally-mediated dispositions to make commitments and to invest in members of their groups evolved because the fitness of those making the investments was linked to the fitness of those in whom they invested, and because the long-term benefits of credibility and a reputation for trustworthiness outweighed the short-term costs of keeping promises and carrying out threats.
Dennis L. Krebs
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- September 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199778232
- eISBN:
- 9780199897261
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199778232.003.0029
- Subject:
- Psychology, Evolutionary Psychology, Social Psychology
This chapter contains a classification of the moral senses and a speculative account of how they originated. It is suggested that a sense of duty originated in the emotional and motivational states ...
More
This chapter contains a classification of the moral senses and a speculative account of how they originated. It is suggested that a sense of duty originated in the emotional and motivational states that induce people to behave in prosocial ways. A sense of rights originated in a consciousness of implicit social norms defining how people are permitted to advance their interests in the context of their groups. Conscience originated in emotional reactions to social sanctions administered by others. Such moral sentiments as gratitude and indignation originated in emotional reactions to prosocial and antisocial behaviors emitted by others. A sense of justice originated as a means of counteracting cheating in cooperative exchanges. Abstract ideas about morality emerged when early humans acquired the ability to reflect on their moral intuitions. Jonathan Haidt’s model of moral decision-making contrasts rational sources of moral judgment with moral intuitions.Less
This chapter contains a classification of the moral senses and a speculative account of how they originated. It is suggested that a sense of duty originated in the emotional and motivational states that induce people to behave in prosocial ways. A sense of rights originated in a consciousness of implicit social norms defining how people are permitted to advance their interests in the context of their groups. Conscience originated in emotional reactions to social sanctions administered by others. Such moral sentiments as gratitude and indignation originated in emotional reactions to prosocial and antisocial behaviors emitted by others. A sense of justice originated as a means of counteracting cheating in cooperative exchanges. Abstract ideas about morality emerged when early humans acquired the ability to reflect on their moral intuitions. Jonathan Haidt’s model of moral decision-making contrasts rational sources of moral judgment with moral intuitions.
R. Jay Wallace
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- January 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199753673
- eISBN:
- 9780199918829
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199753673.003.0015
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
This paper engages critically with the new account of blame that is presented in T. M. Scanlon’s recent work. On Scanlon’s account, blame involves the justified adjustment of an agent’s attitudes in ...
More
This paper engages critically with the new account of blame that is presented in T. M. Scanlon’s recent work. On Scanlon’s account, blame involves the justified adjustment of an agent’s attitudes in response to actions that impair the agent’s relationship with another party. I argue that this approach fails to capture the distinctive force of moral blame, and also that its emphasis on the impairment of relationships leads to a distorted account of the relational dimension of morality. I develop an alternative account of blame in terms of the reactive sentiments (such as resentment, indignation, and guilt), and show why blame, on the account of it I favor, is an important form of response to actions that offend against moral values. The tendency to blame people for moral wrongs is a way of caring about moral ends that is peculiarly appropriate to the relational character of those ends.Less
This paper engages critically with the new account of blame that is presented in T. M. Scanlon’s recent work. On Scanlon’s account, blame involves the justified adjustment of an agent’s attitudes in response to actions that impair the agent’s relationship with another party. I argue that this approach fails to capture the distinctive force of moral blame, and also that its emphasis on the impairment of relationships leads to a distorted account of the relational dimension of morality. I develop an alternative account of blame in terms of the reactive sentiments (such as resentment, indignation, and guilt), and show why blame, on the account of it I favor, is an important form of response to actions that offend against moral values. The tendency to blame people for moral wrongs is a way of caring about moral ends that is peculiarly appropriate to the relational character of those ends.
Thanos Zartaloudis
- Published in print:
- 2019
- Published Online:
- May 2021
- ISBN:
- 9781474442008
- eISBN:
- 9781474459808
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Edinburgh University Press
- DOI:
- 10.3366/edinburgh/9781474442008.003.0005
- Subject:
- Law, Legal History
This chapter examines the relation between nomos and nemesis, a sentiment that arguably entails an early sense of indignation, in the Homeric uses, with some reference to later understandings and the ...
More
This chapter examines the relation between nomos and nemesis, a sentiment that arguably entails an early sense of indignation, in the Homeric uses, with some reference to later understandings and the link to aidōs. It also examines the respective uses in Hediod.Less
This chapter examines the relation between nomos and nemesis, a sentiment that arguably entails an early sense of indignation, in the Homeric uses, with some reference to later understandings and the link to aidōs. It also examines the respective uses in Hediod.
Dana Kay Nelkin
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- September 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199608560
- eISBN:
- 9780191729638
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199608560.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, Moral Philosophy
In this chapter, the rational abilities view is defended from arguments that the ability to do otherwise is required for both praiseworthy and blameworthy actions. The ability to do otherwise has ...
More
In this chapter, the rational abilities view is defended from arguments that the ability to do otherwise is required for both praiseworthy and blameworthy actions. The ability to do otherwise has been thought to be essential for several reasons, including connections to the fairness of blame, to one's being the ultimate source of one's actions, and because it has simply seemed true. In this chapter, variants of each of these challenges is addressed and the rational abilities view is shown to have the resources to answer each. The discussion of fairness of blames leads naturally into questions concerning the fairness of so-called “retributive attitudes,” such as resentment and indignation, as well as the fairness of inflicting harm and punishment, and these questions are also addressed.Less
In this chapter, the rational abilities view is defended from arguments that the ability to do otherwise is required for both praiseworthy and blameworthy actions. The ability to do otherwise has been thought to be essential for several reasons, including connections to the fairness of blame, to one's being the ultimate source of one's actions, and because it has simply seemed true. In this chapter, variants of each of these challenges is addressed and the rational abilities view is shown to have the resources to answer each. The discussion of fairness of blames leads naturally into questions concerning the fairness of so-called “retributive attitudes,” such as resentment and indignation, as well as the fairness of inflicting harm and punishment, and these questions are also addressed.
Jeff Goodwin, James M. Jasper, and Francesca Polletta (eds)
- Published in print:
- 2001
- Published Online:
- February 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780226303987
- eISBN:
- 9780226304007
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226304007.001.0001
- Subject:
- Sociology, Politics, Social Movements and Social Change
Emotions are back. Once at the center of the study of politics, emotions have receded into the shadows during the past three decades, with no place in the rationalistic, structural, and ...
More
Emotions are back. Once at the center of the study of politics, emotions have receded into the shadows during the past three decades, with no place in the rationalistic, structural, and organizational models that dominate academic political analysis. This collection of chapters aims to reverse this trend, reincorporating emotions such as anger, indignation, fear, disgust, joy, and love into research on politics and social protest. The tools of cultural analysis are especially useful for probing the role of emotions in politics, the book argues. Moral outrage, the shame of spoiled collective identities, or the joy of imagining a new and better society, are not automatic responses to events. Rather, they are related to moral institutions, felt obligations and rights, and information about expected effects, all of which are culturally and historically variable.Less
Emotions are back. Once at the center of the study of politics, emotions have receded into the shadows during the past three decades, with no place in the rationalistic, structural, and organizational models that dominate academic political analysis. This collection of chapters aims to reverse this trend, reincorporating emotions such as anger, indignation, fear, disgust, joy, and love into research on politics and social protest. The tools of cultural analysis are especially useful for probing the role of emotions in politics, the book argues. Moral outrage, the shame of spoiled collective identities, or the joy of imagining a new and better society, are not automatic responses to events. Rather, they are related to moral institutions, felt obligations and rights, and information about expected effects, all of which are culturally and historically variable.
Mihaela Mihai
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- September 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780231176507
- eISBN:
- 9780231541183
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Columbia University Press
- DOI:
- 10.7312/columbia/9780231176507.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Political Philosophy
Chapter I provides a positive answer to the question, Why should a society engage with a painful past? By drawing attention to the normative weight — but also to the strategic value — of resentment ...
More
Chapter I provides a positive answer to the question, Why should a society engage with a painful past? By drawing attention to the normative weight — but also to the strategic value — of resentment and indignation as evaluative responses to oppression and injustice, Chapter I dismisses the sceptic’s fear of their destabilising impact on democratisation processes.Less
Chapter I provides a positive answer to the question, Why should a society engage with a painful past? By drawing attention to the normative weight — but also to the strategic value — of resentment and indignation as evaluative responses to oppression and injustice, Chapter I dismisses the sceptic’s fear of their destabilising impact on democratisation processes.
Mihaela Mihai
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- September 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780231176507
- eISBN:
- 9780231541183
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Columbia University Press
- DOI:
- 10.7312/columbia/9780231176507.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Political Philosophy
The Conclusion recapitulates the major arguments, sketches further directions of research, and addresses several potential criticisms. The path forward is to recognise the role that emotions such as ...
More
The Conclusion recapitulates the major arguments, sketches further directions of research, and addresses several potential criticisms. The path forward is to recognise the role that emotions such as resentment and indignation can play in the normative and cultural reproduction of democratic orders at all times, beyond the foundational moment.Less
The Conclusion recapitulates the major arguments, sketches further directions of research, and addresses several potential criticisms. The path forward is to recognise the role that emotions such as resentment and indignation can play in the normative and cultural reproduction of democratic orders at all times, beyond the foundational moment.
Mihaela Mihai
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- September 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780231176507
- eISBN:
- 9780231541183
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Columbia University Press
- DOI:
- 10.7312/columbia/9780231176507.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Political Philosophy
The Introduction formulates the two guiding questions of the book: Do aspiring democracies need to engage with a past of violence? If yes, what institutional form should justice take, given the ...
More
The Introduction formulates the two guiding questions of the book: Do aspiring democracies need to engage with a past of violence? If yes, what institutional form should justice take, given the volatile emotional circumstances of democratic transitions?Less
The Introduction formulates the two guiding questions of the book: Do aspiring democracies need to engage with a past of violence? If yes, what institutional form should justice take, given the volatile emotional circumstances of democratic transitions?
Tim Parks
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- January 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780300215366
- eISBN:
- 9780300216738
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Yale University Press
- DOI:
- 10.12987/yale/9780300215366.003.0009
- Subject:
- Literature, Criticism/Theory
This chapter examines the recurrence of the theme of death in Philip Roth's novels, including Indignation, Exit Ghost, and Nemesis. The draft and the Korean War in Indignation, the 9/11 aftermath and ...
More
This chapter examines the recurrence of the theme of death in Philip Roth's novels, including Indignation, Exit Ghost, and Nemesis. The draft and the Korean War in Indignation, the 9/11 aftermath and Bush reelection in Exit Ghost, and the 1944 polio epidemic in Nemesis interest Roth only insofar as they induce an atmosphere of collective fear. The words “dread,” “terrified,” “frightened,” “scared” “horror,” “jeopardize,” “imperil,” “vulnerable,” “panic” abound in Roth's fiction. Only pages into The Humbling we hear that celebrity actor Simon Axler is “awash with terror and fear.” “Everything gruesome must be squarely faced,” says Axler. This chapter also highlights one figure who persists in Roth's novels: the solid if unimaginative father who provides his family with protection.Less
This chapter examines the recurrence of the theme of death in Philip Roth's novels, including Indignation, Exit Ghost, and Nemesis. The draft and the Korean War in Indignation, the 9/11 aftermath and Bush reelection in Exit Ghost, and the 1944 polio epidemic in Nemesis interest Roth only insofar as they induce an atmosphere of collective fear. The words “dread,” “terrified,” “frightened,” “scared” “horror,” “jeopardize,” “imperil,” “vulnerable,” “panic” abound in Roth's fiction. Only pages into The Humbling we hear that celebrity actor Simon Axler is “awash with terror and fear.” “Everything gruesome must be squarely faced,” says Axler. This chapter also highlights one figure who persists in Roth's novels: the solid if unimaginative father who provides his family with protection.