Stephen Gaukroger
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- January 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199594931
- eISBN:
- 9780191595745
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199594931.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, General
In the course of the eighteenth century, natural philosophy began to take on a new cultural standing, emerging as the paradigm bearer of, and the standard for, cognitive values. It was Fontenelle who ...
More
In the course of the eighteenth century, natural philosophy began to take on a new cultural standing, emerging as the paradigm bearer of, and the standard for, cognitive values. It was Fontenelle who had established the standing of natural philosophy in France as a worthy and useful form of inquiry, but it was Voltaire who had elevated its standing further by making it into the model for cognitive grasp per se. In d'Alembert's preliminary Discours to the Encyclopédie, a more elaborate statement of the archetypal role of natural philosophy in cognitive enquiry was set out.Less
In the course of the eighteenth century, natural philosophy began to take on a new cultural standing, emerging as the paradigm bearer of, and the standard for, cognitive values. It was Fontenelle who had established the standing of natural philosophy in France as a worthy and useful form of inquiry, but it was Voltaire who had elevated its standing further by making it into the model for cognitive grasp per se. In d'Alembert's preliminary Discours to the Encyclopédie, a more elaborate statement of the archetypal role of natural philosophy in cognitive enquiry was set out.
Stephen Gaukroger
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- January 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199594931
- eISBN:
- 9780191595745
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199594931.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, General
The basic assumption of ‘rational mechanics’ was that all natural philosophy was mechanics, and that, as mechanics was pursued with greater and greater detail and sophistication, the rest of natural ...
More
The basic assumption of ‘rational mechanics’ was that all natural philosophy was mechanics, and that, as mechanics was pursued with greater and greater detail and sophistication, the rest of natural philosophy would fall into place around it. The guiding idea, from Varignon and Hermann at the beginning of the eighteenth century, up to d'Alembert and Euler in mid‐century, was that mechanics could be pursued independently of other natural‐philosophical considerations, that it was the one absolutely secure physical discipline because of its mathematical (and effectively a priori) standing. The chapter explores the rational mechanics of d'Alembert and Euler, and questions whether what was proposed in fact had an a priori standing, and whether it was plausible to assume that recalcitrant phenomena such as the refraction of light, the behaviour of fluids, and gravitation could be accounted for by mechanics.Less
The basic assumption of ‘rational mechanics’ was that all natural philosophy was mechanics, and that, as mechanics was pursued with greater and greater detail and sophistication, the rest of natural philosophy would fall into place around it. The guiding idea, from Varignon and Hermann at the beginning of the eighteenth century, up to d'Alembert and Euler in mid‐century, was that mechanics could be pursued independently of other natural‐philosophical considerations, that it was the one absolutely secure physical discipline because of its mathematical (and effectively a priori) standing. The chapter explores the rational mechanics of d'Alembert and Euler, and questions whether what was proposed in fact had an a priori standing, and whether it was plausible to assume that recalcitrant phenomena such as the refraction of light, the behaviour of fluids, and gravitation could be accounted for by mechanics.
Stephen Gaukroger
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- January 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199594931
- eISBN:
- 9780191595745
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199594931.003.0013
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, General
In a context in which traditional religious and humanistic assumptions about universal moral, social, and other values have come loose, the eighteenth‐century employment of developmental stages in ...
More
In a context in which traditional religious and humanistic assumptions about universal moral, social, and other values have come loose, the eighteenth‐century employment of developmental stages in understanding modern institutions takes on a new standing. In particular, d'Alembert's idea that the present is a culmination of and in many respects an inevitable outcome of the past depends on the idea that natural philosophy takes precedence over any other form of understanding. This idea is discussed in the contexts of discussions of the move from myth to reason, in that of the history of manners. Finally, Hume's very different, but equally historically based account of what understanding consists in is contrasted with that of d'Alembert, and the question of the balance between propositional and non‐propositional forms of understanding explored.Less
In a context in which traditional religious and humanistic assumptions about universal moral, social, and other values have come loose, the eighteenth‐century employment of developmental stages in understanding modern institutions takes on a new standing. In particular, d'Alembert's idea that the present is a culmination of and in many respects an inevitable outcome of the past depends on the idea that natural philosophy takes precedence over any other form of understanding. This idea is discussed in the contexts of discussions of the move from myth to reason, in that of the history of manners. Finally, Hume's very different, but equally historically based account of what understanding consists in is contrasted with that of d'Alembert, and the question of the balance between propositional and non‐propositional forms of understanding explored.
Jonathan I. Israel
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780199279227
- eISBN:
- 9780191700040
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199279227.003.0014
- Subject:
- History, History of Ideas, European Modern History
This chapter discusses British Deism, the rejection of republican radicalism, and the French anglicisme in the mid-18th century. Voltaire, Montesquieu, and Maupertuis, the giants among the French ...
More
This chapter discusses British Deism, the rejection of republican radicalism, and the French anglicisme in the mid-18th century. Voltaire, Montesquieu, and Maupertuis, the giants among the French philosophes in the mid 1740s, were, in various ways, all ardent protagonists of the ‘British Enlightenment’. Around 1745, the movement which d’Alembert dubbed anglicisme was indeed at its zenith, with d’Alembert himself frequently extolling Newton and Locke in these years while the young Diderot joined in with his part translation and part reworking of Shaftesbury’s Inquiry Concerning Virtue (1699), published in 1745.Less
This chapter discusses British Deism, the rejection of republican radicalism, and the French anglicisme in the mid-18th century. Voltaire, Montesquieu, and Maupertuis, the giants among the French philosophes in the mid 1740s, were, in various ways, all ardent protagonists of the ‘British Enlightenment’. Around 1745, the movement which d’Alembert dubbed anglicisme was indeed at its zenith, with d’Alembert himself frequently extolling Newton and Locke in these years while the young Diderot joined in with his part translation and part reworking of Shaftesbury’s Inquiry Concerning Virtue (1699), published in 1745.
Genevieve Lloyd
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- September 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199669561
- eISBN:
- 9780191757013
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199669561.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
The idea of the Enlightenment has become a touchstone for emotional and often contradictory articulations of contemporary western values. Enlightenment Shadows is a study of the place of ...
More
The idea of the Enlightenment has become a touchstone for emotional and often contradictory articulations of contemporary western values. Enlightenment Shadows is a study of the place of Enlightenment thought in intellectual history and of its continued relevance. It focuses especially on what is distinctive in ideas of intellectual character offered by key Enlightenment thinkers—on their attitudes to belief and scepticism; on their optimism about the future; and on the uncertainties and instabilities which nonetheless often lurk beneath their use of imagery of light. The book is organized around interconnected close readings of a range of texts: Montesquieu’s Persian Letters; Voltaire’s Philosophical Dictionary; Hume’s essay ‘The Sceptic’; Adam Smith’s treatment of sympathy and imagination in Theory of Moral Sentiments; d’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia—together with Diderot’s entry on Encyclopedia; Diderot’s Rameau’s Nephew; and Kant’s essay Perpetual Peace. Throughout, the readings highlight ways in which Enlightenment thinkers enacted in their writing—and reflected on—the interplay of intellect, imagination, and emotion. Recurring themes include: the nature of judgement—its relations with imagination and with ideals of objectivity; issues of truth and relativism; the ethical significance of imagining one’s self into the situations of others; cosmopolitanism; tolerance; and the idea of the secular.Less
The idea of the Enlightenment has become a touchstone for emotional and often contradictory articulations of contemporary western values. Enlightenment Shadows is a study of the place of Enlightenment thought in intellectual history and of its continued relevance. It focuses especially on what is distinctive in ideas of intellectual character offered by key Enlightenment thinkers—on their attitudes to belief and scepticism; on their optimism about the future; and on the uncertainties and instabilities which nonetheless often lurk beneath their use of imagery of light. The book is organized around interconnected close readings of a range of texts: Montesquieu’s Persian Letters; Voltaire’s Philosophical Dictionary; Hume’s essay ‘The Sceptic’; Adam Smith’s treatment of sympathy and imagination in Theory of Moral Sentiments; d’Alembert’s Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia—together with Diderot’s entry on Encyclopedia; Diderot’s Rameau’s Nephew; and Kant’s essay Perpetual Peace. Throughout, the readings highlight ways in which Enlightenment thinkers enacted in their writing—and reflected on—the interplay of intellect, imagination, and emotion. Recurring themes include: the nature of judgement—its relations with imagination and with ideals of objectivity; issues of truth and relativism; the ethical significance of imagining one’s self into the situations of others; cosmopolitanism; tolerance; and the idea of the secular.
John W. Yolton
- Published in print:
- 1991
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198242741
- eISBN:
- 9780191680557
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198242741.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
This chapter explores some of the writings of the better-known French writers, many of whom were associated with Diderot and d'Alembert in the great Encyclopédie; others, such as La Mettrie and ...
More
This chapter explores some of the writings of the better-known French writers, many of whom were associated with Diderot and d'Alembert in the great Encyclopédie; others, such as La Mettrie and d'Holbach, contributed to what is usually thought of as ‘French Materialism’. Locke's name is found in some of these writings, especially in Diderot's ‘defence of the Abbé de Prades and in his Encyclopédie entry ‘Locke’. The chapter is not only concerned with Locke's name and doctrines among the French ‘philosophes’. It seeks to fill in from these sources the continued debate over the three systems of mind and body; the active concept of matter, especially biological matter; and the concept of materialism. It determines whether this French materialism—the materialism of the ‘philosophes’—differs in significant ways from the materialism and automatism feared by British writers who attacked Locke.Less
This chapter explores some of the writings of the better-known French writers, many of whom were associated with Diderot and d'Alembert in the great Encyclopédie; others, such as La Mettrie and d'Holbach, contributed to what is usually thought of as ‘French Materialism’. Locke's name is found in some of these writings, especially in Diderot's ‘defence of the Abbé de Prades and in his Encyclopédie entry ‘Locke’. The chapter is not only concerned with Locke's name and doctrines among the French ‘philosophes’. It seeks to fill in from these sources the continued debate over the three systems of mind and body; the active concept of matter, especially biological matter; and the concept of materialism. It determines whether this French materialism—the materialism of the ‘philosophes’—differs in significant ways from the materialism and automatism feared by British writers who attacked Locke.
Peter Szendy
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- May 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780823267057
- eISBN:
- 9780823272303
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Fordham University Press
- DOI:
- 10.5422/fordham/9780823267057.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics
A reading of some of Diderot’s texts (particularly Rameau’s Nephew) brings us to resume an old figure of rhetoric: effictio, in other words the description of a fictive body that still begins to ...
More
A reading of some of Diderot’s texts (particularly Rameau’s Nephew) brings us to resume an old figure of rhetoric: effictio, in other words the description of a fictive body that still begins to exist, in effects.Less
A reading of some of Diderot’s texts (particularly Rameau’s Nephew) brings us to resume an old figure of rhetoric: effictio, in other words the description of a fictive body that still begins to exist, in effects.
S. G. Rajeev
- Published in print:
- 2018
- Published Online:
- October 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780198805021
- eISBN:
- 9780191843136
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198805021.003.0007
- Subject:
- Physics, Soft Matter / Biological Physics, Condensed Matter Physics / Materials
It is found experimentally that all the components of fluid velocity (not just thenormal component) vanish at a wall. No matter how small the viscosity, the large velocity gradients near a wall ...
More
It is found experimentally that all the components of fluid velocity (not just thenormal component) vanish at a wall. No matter how small the viscosity, the large velocity gradients near a wall invalidate Euler’s equations. Prandtl proposed that viscosity has negligible effect except near a thin region near a wall. Prandtl’s equations simplify the Navier-Stokes equation in this boundary layer, by ignoring one dimension. They have an unusual scale invariance in which the distances along the boundary and perpendicular to it have different dimensions. Using this symmetry, Blasius reduced Prandtl’s equations to one dimension. They can then be solved numerically. A convergent analytic approximation was also found by H. Weyl. The drag on a flat plate can now be derived, resolving d’Alembert’s paradox. When the boundary is too long, Prandtl’s theory breaks down: the boundary layer becomes turbulent or separates from the wall.Less
It is found experimentally that all the components of fluid velocity (not just thenormal component) vanish at a wall. No matter how small the viscosity, the large velocity gradients near a wall invalidate Euler’s equations. Prandtl proposed that viscosity has negligible effect except near a thin region near a wall. Prandtl’s equations simplify the Navier-Stokes equation in this boundary layer, by ignoring one dimension. They have an unusual scale invariance in which the distances along the boundary and perpendicular to it have different dimensions. Using this symmetry, Blasius reduced Prandtl’s equations to one dimension. They can then be solved numerically. A convergent analytic approximation was also found by H. Weyl. The drag on a flat plate can now be derived, resolving d’Alembert’s paradox. When the boundary is too long, Prandtl’s theory breaks down: the boundary layer becomes turbulent or separates from the wall.
Angelica Goodden
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- January 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199683833
- eISBN:
- 9780191766190
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199683833.003.0005
- Subject:
- Literature, 16th-century and Renaissance Literature, European Literature
This chapter details Rousseau's writing of and on drama, and dwells on the Lettre à d’Alembert's contrasting the effects of playgoing with the moral benefits of daily life in theatre-free, ...
More
This chapter details Rousseau's writing of and on drama, and dwells on the Lettre à d’Alembert's contrasting the effects of playgoing with the moral benefits of daily life in theatre-free, craft-loving communities such as Geneva's. His ambivalence towards other forms of leisure is explored, and again linked with his utilitarian theory of art. The writing and hand-copying of La Nouvelle Héloïse is described along with his defence of the book's moral ambiguities.Less
This chapter details Rousseau's writing of and on drama, and dwells on the Lettre à d’Alembert's contrasting the effects of playgoing with the moral benefits of daily life in theatre-free, craft-loving communities such as Geneva's. His ambivalence towards other forms of leisure is explored, and again linked with his utilitarian theory of art. The writing and hand-copying of La Nouvelle Héloïse is described along with his defence of the book's moral ambiguities.
J.B. Shank
- Published in print:
- 2018
- Published Online:
- May 2019
- ISBN:
- 9780226509297
- eISBN:
- 9780226509327
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226509327.003.0011
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
This Coda closes the book by reflecting on the initial reception of Newton's Principia in France as it relates to the eruption after 1715 of the "Newton Wars," and the very different understanding of ...
More
This Coda closes the book by reflecting on the initial reception of Newton's Principia in France as it relates to the eruption after 1715 of the "Newton Wars," and the very different understanding of the Principia that sustained them. Stressing the contingent nature of this history, the chapter explores how French science was shaped overall by the peculiar dynamics of Newton's influence. Noting how eighteenth-century mathematicians in the United Kingdom tended to follow the Old Style mathematicians in France in their rejection of mathematical analysis, the irony of the French origin of what we now call "Newtonian mechanics" through a failure to follow Newton as literally as his English and Scottish colleagues is noted. The emergence of Newton's new identity as a mathematical natural philosopher and defender of the theory of universal gravitation after 1715 is also explored, along with the changing French understanding of the Principia and its place in French science. Pointing to The Newton Wars and the Beginning of the French Enlightenment, which picks up the story from here, the book concludes by pointing to some of the ways that Enlightenment French Newtonianism as practiced after 1730 reveal the historical traces of this earlier history.Less
This Coda closes the book by reflecting on the initial reception of Newton's Principia in France as it relates to the eruption after 1715 of the "Newton Wars," and the very different understanding of the Principia that sustained them. Stressing the contingent nature of this history, the chapter explores how French science was shaped overall by the peculiar dynamics of Newton's influence. Noting how eighteenth-century mathematicians in the United Kingdom tended to follow the Old Style mathematicians in France in their rejection of mathematical analysis, the irony of the French origin of what we now call "Newtonian mechanics" through a failure to follow Newton as literally as his English and Scottish colleagues is noted. The emergence of Newton's new identity as a mathematical natural philosopher and defender of the theory of universal gravitation after 1715 is also explored, along with the changing French understanding of the Principia and its place in French science. Pointing to The Newton Wars and the Beginning of the French Enlightenment, which picks up the story from here, the book concludes by pointing to some of the ways that Enlightenment French Newtonianism as practiced after 1730 reveal the historical traces of this earlier history.
Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe
- Published in print:
- 2019
- Published Online:
- September 2019
- ISBN:
- 9780823282340
- eISBN:
- 9780823286201
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Fordham University Press
- DOI:
- 10.5422/fordham/9780823282340.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
This chapter continues the argument from the previous chapter, developing it through a more detailed reading of the Letter to d’Alembert on the Theater, in which Rousseau’s well known condemnation of ...
More
This chapter continues the argument from the previous chapter, developing it through a more detailed reading of the Letter to d’Alembert on the Theater, in which Rousseau’s well known condemnation of the theater occurs. Lacoue-Labarthe argues that Rousseau in fact does not condemn imitation as such, his target being rather imitation that seeks to produce effects of pleasure and complacency by way of flattering identifications. It is in this light that Rousseau critiques catharsis as a harmful illusion of relief from evil that leaves the evil in place. But when one turns to what Rousseau says about tragedy, and Greek tragedy in particular, another perspective emerges: catharsis and Aufhebung as a speculative sublation of historically embedded conflicts. Greek tragedy was not merely theater, but the staging of a originary agon between two kinds of “Greece,” one of which is absolutely anterior to theater as such and so is purely archaic. In this sense, Greek tragedy for Rousseau is a philosophical scene par excellence, the scene of a historical dialectic.Less
This chapter continues the argument from the previous chapter, developing it through a more detailed reading of the Letter to d’Alembert on the Theater, in which Rousseau’s well known condemnation of the theater occurs. Lacoue-Labarthe argues that Rousseau in fact does not condemn imitation as such, his target being rather imitation that seeks to produce effects of pleasure and complacency by way of flattering identifications. It is in this light that Rousseau critiques catharsis as a harmful illusion of relief from evil that leaves the evil in place. But when one turns to what Rousseau says about tragedy, and Greek tragedy in particular, another perspective emerges: catharsis and Aufhebung as a speculative sublation of historically embedded conflicts. Greek tragedy was not merely theater, but the staging of a originary agon between two kinds of “Greece,” one of which is absolutely anterior to theater as such and so is purely archaic. In this sense, Greek tragedy for Rousseau is a philosophical scene par excellence, the scene of a historical dialectic.
Genevieve Lloyd
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- September 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199669561
- eISBN:
- 9780191757013
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199669561.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy
The chapter opens with a discussion of metaphors of light and of motion in Bacon’s essay On Truth, leading into an examination of the tensions between timelessness and change in the Enlightenment ...
More
The chapter opens with a discussion of metaphors of light and of motion in Bacon’s essay On Truth, leading into an examination of the tensions between timelessness and change in the Enlightenment understanding of knowledge. Those tensions surface in reflections which d’Alembert and Diderot offered on conceptual aspects of their Encyclopedia project—concerned both with displaying the timeless structure of the human mind and, on the other hand, emphasizing what is new in the understanding of knowledge in their own time. Central to the discussion is Diderot’s approach to judgement, which he sees as involved both in the understanding of genius in the arts, and in the selection and ordering of subject entries in the Encyclopedia. The chapter concludes with a comparison of Diderot’s concept of genius with the account of judgement offered by Kant in his third Critique. Less
The chapter opens with a discussion of metaphors of light and of motion in Bacon’s essay On Truth, leading into an examination of the tensions between timelessness and change in the Enlightenment understanding of knowledge. Those tensions surface in reflections which d’Alembert and Diderot offered on conceptual aspects of their Encyclopedia project—concerned both with displaying the timeless structure of the human mind and, on the other hand, emphasizing what is new in the understanding of knowledge in their own time. Central to the discussion is Diderot’s approach to judgement, which he sees as involved both in the understanding of genius in the arts, and in the selection and ordering of subject entries in the Encyclopedia. The chapter concludes with a comparison of Diderot’s concept of genius with the account of judgement offered by Kant in his third Critique.
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- March 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780226749457
- eISBN:
- 9780226749471
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226749471.003.0009
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
Too many historians have recognized Denis Diderot and Jean le Rond d'Alembert's Encyclopédie as the defining text of the French Enlightenment. Just as many have argued that the project's initial ...
More
Too many historians have recognized Denis Diderot and Jean le Rond d'Alembert's Encyclopédie as the defining text of the French Enlightenment. Just as many have argued that the project's initial publication, scandalous reception, and eventual prohibition were the key catalysts in the formation of the Enlightenment as a French social movement. What has not often been stressed, however, is that these undeniably transformative events also completed a half-century process of intellectual and social change in France. This coda proposes, not a reinterpretation of the history of the Encyclopédie, but a retelling of this familiar story in ways that highlight how it served both as the climax of Isaac Newton's reception in eighteenth-century France and, seamlessly, as the final stitch between this reception and the beginning of the French Enlightenment.Less
Too many historians have recognized Denis Diderot and Jean le Rond d'Alembert's Encyclopédie as the defining text of the French Enlightenment. Just as many have argued that the project's initial publication, scandalous reception, and eventual prohibition were the key catalysts in the formation of the Enlightenment as a French social movement. What has not often been stressed, however, is that these undeniably transformative events also completed a half-century process of intellectual and social change in France. This coda proposes, not a reinterpretation of the history of the Encyclopédie, but a retelling of this familiar story in ways that highlight how it served both as the climax of Isaac Newton's reception in eighteenth-century France and, seamlessly, as the final stitch between this reception and the beginning of the French Enlightenment.
Olivier Darrigol
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- June 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780198712886
- eISBN:
- 9780191781360
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198712886.003.0001
- Subject:
- Physics, History of Physics
This chapter is a history of necessity arguments in classical mechanics, including the seventeenth-century opposition between Descartes’s rationalism and Newton’s empiricism, the rationalism of ...
More
This chapter is a history of necessity arguments in classical mechanics, including the seventeenth-century opposition between Descartes’s rationalism and Newton’s empiricism, the rationalism of earlier statics since Archimedes, the varieties of rationalism defended by Leibniz, Euler, and d’Alembert in the eighteenth century, and the nineteenth-century persistence of a few deductive arguments against the empiricist tide. Some of the rational derivations of the laws of mechanics relied on theological arguments; others were of a more conceptual nature. They often were very ingenious. Despite evident flaws, they all contributed to a restructuration of mechanics and to a better understanding of its foundations.Less
This chapter is a history of necessity arguments in classical mechanics, including the seventeenth-century opposition between Descartes’s rationalism and Newton’s empiricism, the rationalism of earlier statics since Archimedes, the varieties of rationalism defended by Leibniz, Euler, and d’Alembert in the eighteenth century, and the nineteenth-century persistence of a few deductive arguments against the empiricist tide. Some of the rational derivations of the laws of mechanics relied on theological arguments; others were of a more conceptual nature. They often were very ingenious. Despite evident flaws, they all contributed to a restructuration of mechanics and to a better understanding of its foundations.
Olivier Darrigol
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- June 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780198712886
- eISBN:
- 9780191781360
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198712886.003.0002
- Subject:
- Physics, History of Physics
This chapter combines some assumptions of the rationalist founders of mechanics (the impossibility of perpetual motion, the causal relation between force and motion, the relativity principle, and ...
More
This chapter combines some assumptions of the rationalist founders of mechanics (the impossibility of perpetual motion, the causal relation between force and motion, the relativity principle, and what I call the secularity principle) with the definitions of four classes of ideal mechanical systems (connected systems, particles acting at a distance, continuous media, colliding particles) in order to derive the laws of equilibrium and motion of these systems. The usual laws of mechanics are retrieved in each case. The conclusion is that classical mechanics is the only theory of motion complying with a few natural requirements on the comprehensibility of motion at the macroscopic scale.Less
This chapter combines some assumptions of the rationalist founders of mechanics (the impossibility of perpetual motion, the causal relation between force and motion, the relativity principle, and what I call the secularity principle) with the definitions of four classes of ideal mechanical systems (connected systems, particles acting at a distance, continuous media, colliding particles) in order to derive the laws of equilibrium and motion of these systems. The usual laws of mechanics are retrieved in each case. The conclusion is that classical mechanics is the only theory of motion complying with a few natural requirements on the comprehensibility of motion at the macroscopic scale.
Wayne C. Myrvold
- Published in print:
- 2021
- Published Online:
- February 2021
- ISBN:
- 9780198865094
- eISBN:
- 9780191897481
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198865094.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
This chapter engages in some ground-clearing. Two concepts have been proposed to play the role of objective probability. One is associated with the idea that probability involves mere counting of ...
More
This chapter engages in some ground-clearing. Two concepts have been proposed to play the role of objective probability. One is associated with the idea that probability involves mere counting of possibilities (often wrongly attributed to Laplace). The other is frequentism, the idea that probability can be defined as long-run relative frequency in some actual or hypothetical sequence of events. Associated with the idea that probability is merely a matter of counting of possibilities is a temptation to believe that there is a principle, called the Principle of Indifference, which can generate probabilities out of ignorance. In this chapter the reasons that neither of these approaches can achieve its goal are rehearsed, with reference to historical discussions in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. It includes some of the prehistory of discussions of what has come to be known, misleadingly, as Bertrand’s paradox.Less
This chapter engages in some ground-clearing. Two concepts have been proposed to play the role of objective probability. One is associated with the idea that probability involves mere counting of possibilities (often wrongly attributed to Laplace). The other is frequentism, the idea that probability can be defined as long-run relative frequency in some actual or hypothetical sequence of events. Associated with the idea that probability is merely a matter of counting of possibilities is a temptation to believe that there is a principle, called the Principle of Indifference, which can generate probabilities out of ignorance. In this chapter the reasons that neither of these approaches can achieve its goal are rehearsed, with reference to historical discussions in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. It includes some of the prehistory of discussions of what has come to be known, misleadingly, as Bertrand’s paradox.
Jennifer Coopersmith
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- June 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198743040
- eISBN:
- 9780191802966
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198743040.003.0001
- Subject:
- Physics, Particle Physics / Astrophysics / Cosmology, History of Physics
The chapter explains how the Principle of Least Action yields a unique answer to a physical problem irrespective of the frame of reference. The motivation arises from d’Alembert’s rousing words: “To ...
More
The chapter explains how the Principle of Least Action yields a unique answer to a physical problem irrespective of the frame of reference. The motivation arises from d’Alembert’s rousing words: “To someone who could grasp the Universe from a unified standpoint the entire creation would appear as a unique truth and necessity.” The requirement is that one “algorithm” can cope with all the specificity, variety, and complexity across the whole of physics. That one algorithm could ever be up to the task is made plausible by use of an allegory involving a King, the princess, and some suitors. Finally, the link with Least Action is made. Note that the terms extremal, objectivity, observer, and viewpoint are explained.Less
The chapter explains how the Principle of Least Action yields a unique answer to a physical problem irrespective of the frame of reference. The motivation arises from d’Alembert’s rousing words: “To someone who could grasp the Universe from a unified standpoint the entire creation would appear as a unique truth and necessity.” The requirement is that one “algorithm” can cope with all the specificity, variety, and complexity across the whole of physics. That one algorithm could ever be up to the task is made plausible by use of an allegory involving a King, the princess, and some suitors. Finally, the link with Least Action is made. Note that the terms extremal, objectivity, observer, and viewpoint are explained.
Jennifer Coopersmith
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- June 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198743040
- eISBN:
- 9780191802966
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198743040.003.0005
- Subject:
- Physics, Particle Physics / Astrophysics / Cosmology, History of Physics
It is explained how the mysterious Principle of Virtual Work in statics is extended to the even more mysterious Principle of d’Alembert’s in dynamics. This is achieved by d’Alembert’s far-sighted ...
More
It is explained how the mysterious Principle of Virtual Work in statics is extended to the even more mysterious Principle of d’Alembert’s in dynamics. This is achieved by d’Alembert’s far-sighted stratagem: considering a reversed massy acceleration as an inertial force. A worked example is given (the half-Atwood machine or “black box”). Some counter-intuitive aspects are made intuitive by more examples: the Pluto-Charon system of orbiting planets; Newton’s and then Mach’s explanation of Newton’s bucket. Also, it is demonstrated that the law of the conservation of energy actually follows from d’Alembert’s Principle. The reader is alerted to the astoundingly fundamental nature of d’Alembert’s Principle. It is the cornerstone of classical, relativistic, and quantum mechanics. As Lanczos writes: “All the different principles of mechanics are merely mathematically different formulations of d’Alembert’s Principle”.Less
It is explained how the mysterious Principle of Virtual Work in statics is extended to the even more mysterious Principle of d’Alembert’s in dynamics. This is achieved by d’Alembert’s far-sighted stratagem: considering a reversed massy acceleration as an inertial force. A worked example is given (the half-Atwood machine or “black box”). Some counter-intuitive aspects are made intuitive by more examples: the Pluto-Charon system of orbiting planets; Newton’s and then Mach’s explanation of Newton’s bucket. Also, it is demonstrated that the law of the conservation of energy actually follows from d’Alembert’s Principle. The reader is alerted to the astoundingly fundamental nature of d’Alembert’s Principle. It is the cornerstone of classical, relativistic, and quantum mechanics. As Lanczos writes: “All the different principles of mechanics are merely mathematically different formulations of d’Alembert’s Principle”.
Jennifer Coopersmith
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- August 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780198716747
- eISBN:
- 9780191800955
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198716747.003.0007
- Subject:
- Physics, Particle Physics / Astrophysics / Cosmology, History of Physics
Vis viva (kinetic energy) was discovered by Leibniz, and ‘s Gravesande’s experiments showed that both momentum and kinetic energy were important measures. The concept of ‘potential energy’ slowly ...
More
Vis viva (kinetic energy) was discovered by Leibniz, and ‘s Gravesande’s experiments showed that both momentum and kinetic energy were important measures. The concept of ‘potential energy’ slowly emerged (from the works of Parent, the Bernoullis, Clairaut, and Laplace). Daniel Bernoulli was the first to understand ‘energy’ in a modern way—as kinetic and potential energy, but also as a source of fuel for engines. He managed to calculate the amount of ‘live force’ in air, introducing the formula ‘integral over PdV’. Maupertuis, Euler, and Lagrange brought in a new idea—the Principle of Least Action, and Lagrange developed a new generalized mechanics using this principle. The Newtonian ‘force approach’ and the Lagrangian ‘energy approach’ are compared and contrasted; and the reason why ‘T – V’ is as important as ‘T + V’ is explained. It is shown that Newton missed discovering energy.Less
Vis viva (kinetic energy) was discovered by Leibniz, and ‘s Gravesande’s experiments showed that both momentum and kinetic energy were important measures. The concept of ‘potential energy’ slowly emerged (from the works of Parent, the Bernoullis, Clairaut, and Laplace). Daniel Bernoulli was the first to understand ‘energy’ in a modern way—as kinetic and potential energy, but also as a source of fuel for engines. He managed to calculate the amount of ‘live force’ in air, introducing the formula ‘integral over PdV’. Maupertuis, Euler, and Lagrange brought in a new idea—the Principle of Least Action, and Lagrange developed a new generalized mechanics using this principle. The Newtonian ‘force approach’ and the Lagrangian ‘energy approach’ are compared and contrasted; and the reason why ‘T – V’ is as important as ‘T + V’ is explained. It is shown that Newton missed discovering energy.
Cynthia Verba
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- November 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780199381029
- eISBN:
- 9780199381043
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199381029.003.0004
- Subject:
- Music, History, Western
There was considerable agreement among the philosophes that Rameau had achieved a breakthrough in music theory precisely because of his application of scientific principles. Despite this consensus, ...
More
There was considerable agreement among the philosophes that Rameau had achieved a breakthrough in music theory precisely because of his application of scientific principles. Despite this consensus, however, the realm of music as science underwent a series of conflicts or debates that were closely analogous to those in the aesthetic realm. Whether the subject was art or science, the Cartesian concept of truth or knowledge—still widely accepted in France until well into the eighteenth century—was increasingly exposed to serious scrutiny or challenge. A principal concern of this chapter is the gradual breakdown of Cartesian rationalism within the scientific realm of music and with d’Alembert’s promotion of Newtonian empirical science. It will be shown that Rameau himself contributed to that breakdown—that despite his Cartesian claims and rhetoric, it was musical practice that ultimately determined his rules and laws of harmony.Less
There was considerable agreement among the philosophes that Rameau had achieved a breakthrough in music theory precisely because of his application of scientific principles. Despite this consensus, however, the realm of music as science underwent a series of conflicts or debates that were closely analogous to those in the aesthetic realm. Whether the subject was art or science, the Cartesian concept of truth or knowledge—still widely accepted in France until well into the eighteenth century—was increasingly exposed to serious scrutiny or challenge. A principal concern of this chapter is the gradual breakdown of Cartesian rationalism within the scientific realm of music and with d’Alembert’s promotion of Newtonian empirical science. It will be shown that Rameau himself contributed to that breakdown—that despite his Cartesian claims and rhetoric, it was musical practice that ultimately determined his rules and laws of harmony.