George Sher
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- September 2006
- ISBN:
- 9780195187427
- eISBN:
- 9780199786596
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195187423.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
Blame is an unpopular and neglected notion: it goes against the grain of a therapeutically oriented culture and has been far less discussed by philosophers than such related notions as responsibility ...
More
Blame is an unpopular and neglected notion: it goes against the grain of a therapeutically oriented culture and has been far less discussed by philosophers than such related notions as responsibility and punishment. This book seeks to show that neither the opposition nor the neglect is justified. The book’s most important conclusion is that blame is inseparable from morality itself — that any considerations that justify us in accepting a set of moral principles must also call for the condemnation of those who violate the principles. Because blame has not received much sustained attention, the book works its way toward its conclusions by first raising, and then seeking to resolve, a series of conceptual and normative questions. These questions include: How are blameworthy acts related to the characters of the agents who perform them? Can agents deserve blame for their bad traits as well as their bad acts? Is blame best understood as a kind of action, a kind of belief, a kind of feeling, a combination of these elements, or something entirely different? What sort of moral concept is blameworthiness? How do blame and blameworthiness — correlative concepts — fit together? Although the book draws both on Hume’s treatment of the relation between character and blame and Strawson’s landmark discussion of the “reactive attitudes”, the theory that emerges is neither Humean nor Strawsonian. It is a new theory that seeks to do more justice than its predecessors to the indispensable role that blame plays in our moral lives.Less
Blame is an unpopular and neglected notion: it goes against the grain of a therapeutically oriented culture and has been far less discussed by philosophers than such related notions as responsibility and punishment. This book seeks to show that neither the opposition nor the neglect is justified. The book’s most important conclusion is that blame is inseparable from morality itself — that any considerations that justify us in accepting a set of moral principles must also call for the condemnation of those who violate the principles. Because blame has not received much sustained attention, the book works its way toward its conclusions by first raising, and then seeking to resolve, a series of conceptual and normative questions. These questions include: How are blameworthy acts related to the characters of the agents who perform them? Can agents deserve blame for their bad traits as well as their bad acts? Is blame best understood as a kind of action, a kind of belief, a kind of feeling, a combination of these elements, or something entirely different? What sort of moral concept is blameworthiness? How do blame and blameworthiness — correlative concepts — fit together? Although the book draws both on Hume’s treatment of the relation between character and blame and Strawson’s landmark discussion of the “reactive attitudes”, the theory that emerges is neither Humean nor Strawsonian. It is a new theory that seeks to do more justice than its predecessors to the indispensable role that blame plays in our moral lives.
Martha Klein
- Published in print:
- 1990
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198248347
- eISBN:
- 9780191681134
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198248347.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This book casts new light on the classic dispute between ‘compatibilists’ and ‘incompatibilists’ about determinism and moral responsibility. The book argues that the traditional account of the ...
More
This book casts new light on the classic dispute between ‘compatibilists’ and ‘incompatibilists’ about determinism and moral responsibility. The book argues that the traditional account of the dispute, turning as it does on the notion of the agent's ‘ability to have acted otherwise’, misrepresents the real disagreement, which arises from the compatibilists' conviction that it is sufficient for blameworthiness that an agent's wrongdoing was the result of a morally reprehensible frame of mind, and the incompatibilists' insistence that wrongdoers cannot be morally responsible for their actions if they are not responsible for their motivating desires and beliefs. The incompatibilist position seems compelling when, for instance, we consider wrongdoers whose desires and attitudes can be traced to early emotional deprivation. The book argues that our response to these and other ‘problem cases’ commits us to an incompatibilist condition for blameworthiness that is actually unfulfillable. In the book's view, however, some reflections on emotional deprivation should also encourage acceptance of a compatibilist condition that will satisfy our desire to be just more fully than the usual proposals emanating from either side of the debate.Less
This book casts new light on the classic dispute between ‘compatibilists’ and ‘incompatibilists’ about determinism and moral responsibility. The book argues that the traditional account of the dispute, turning as it does on the notion of the agent's ‘ability to have acted otherwise’, misrepresents the real disagreement, which arises from the compatibilists' conviction that it is sufficient for blameworthiness that an agent's wrongdoing was the result of a morally reprehensible frame of mind, and the incompatibilists' insistence that wrongdoers cannot be morally responsible for their actions if they are not responsible for their motivating desires and beliefs. The incompatibilist position seems compelling when, for instance, we consider wrongdoers whose desires and attitudes can be traced to early emotional deprivation. The book argues that our response to these and other ‘problem cases’ commits us to an incompatibilist condition for blameworthiness that is actually unfulfillable. In the book's view, however, some reflections on emotional deprivation should also encourage acceptance of a compatibilist condition that will satisfy our desire to be just more fully than the usual proposals emanating from either side of the debate.
George Sher
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- September 2006
- ISBN:
- 9780195187427
- eISBN:
- 9780199786596
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195187423.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This final chapter develops an account of blameworthiness that dovetails with the previous chapter’s account of blame. Because the core constituents of blame consist of a desire and a belief, the ...
More
This final chapter develops an account of blameworthiness that dovetails with the previous chapter’s account of blame. Because the core constituents of blame consist of a desire and a belief, the norms that determine when blame is called for are the ones that correspond to these elements. On the resulting account, blame is called for when (a) the blamer’s belief that the blamee has acted badly is true, and (b) the blamer’s desire that the blamee not have violated a moral principle to which the blamer is committed is justified by the very considerations that justify his commitment itself. By thus making explicit the link between the justification of blame and the justification of the moral principle that the blamee has flouted, we come to see that a commitment to blame is inseparable from a commitment to morality itself.Less
This final chapter develops an account of blameworthiness that dovetails with the previous chapter’s account of blame. Because the core constituents of blame consist of a desire and a belief, the norms that determine when blame is called for are the ones that correspond to these elements. On the resulting account, blame is called for when (a) the blamer’s belief that the blamee has acted badly is true, and (b) the blamer’s desire that the blamee not have violated a moral principle to which the blamer is committed is justified by the very considerations that justify his commitment itself. By thus making explicit the link between the justification of blame and the justification of the moral principle that the blamee has flouted, we come to see that a commitment to blame is inseparable from a commitment to morality itself.
James R. Beebe
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199693702
- eISBN:
- 9780191741265
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199693702.003.0010
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Metaphysics/Epistemology
Drawing upon work in experimental philosophy and evolutionary game theory, the chapter argues that one of the roles the concept of knowledge plays in our social cognitive ecology is that of enabling ...
More
Drawing upon work in experimental philosophy and evolutionary game theory, the chapter argues that one of the roles the concept of knowledge plays in our social cognitive ecology is that of enabling us to make adaptively important distinctions between different kinds of blameworthy and blameless behaviors. In particular, the chapter defends the view that knowledge enables us to distinguish which agents are most worthy of blame for inflicting harms, violating social norms, or cheating in situations of social exchange.Less
Drawing upon work in experimental philosophy and evolutionary game theory, the chapter argues that one of the roles the concept of knowledge plays in our social cognitive ecology is that of enabling us to make adaptively important distinctions between different kinds of blameworthy and blameless behaviors. In particular, the chapter defends the view that knowledge enables us to distinguish which agents are most worthy of blame for inflicting harms, violating social norms, or cheating in situations of social exchange.
Michael McKenna
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- May 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199740031
- eISBN:
- 9780199918706
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199740031.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, General
There are different kinds of responsibility, and even different kinds of moral responsibility. This chapter offers a conceptual map of moral responsibility in the accountability sense. In this sense, ...
More
There are different kinds of responsibility, and even different kinds of moral responsibility. This chapter offers a conceptual map of moral responsibility in the accountability sense. In this sense, those who are morally responsible are candidates for being held to account for what they do. Moral responsibility, so understood, can be explained by three related concepts: morally responsible agency, being morally responsible for something, and holding morally responsible. Morally responsible agents are distinguished from mere moral agents in that they are able to understand and respond to expectations and demands of those holding morally responsible. Being morally responsible for an action in the sense of being blameworthy for it is explained by focusing on morally wrong acts knowingly and freely preformed. A requirement on blameworthiness is that an agent act from a morally objectionable quality of will. Holding morally responsible for a blameworthy act by blaming is distinguished from merely judging that a person is blameworthy insofar as holding blaming involves an attitude of disapproval.Less
There are different kinds of responsibility, and even different kinds of moral responsibility. This chapter offers a conceptual map of moral responsibility in the accountability sense. In this sense, those who are morally responsible are candidates for being held to account for what they do. Moral responsibility, so understood, can be explained by three related concepts: morally responsible agency, being morally responsible for something, and holding morally responsible. Morally responsible agents are distinguished from mere moral agents in that they are able to understand and respond to expectations and demands of those holding morally responsible. Being morally responsible for an action in the sense of being blameworthy for it is explained by focusing on morally wrong acts knowingly and freely preformed. A requirement on blameworthiness is that an agent act from a morally objectionable quality of will. Holding morally responsible for a blameworthy act by blaming is distinguished from merely judging that a person is blameworthy insofar as holding blaming involves an attitude of disapproval.
Joseph Raz
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199599325
- eISBN:
- 9780191741500
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199599325.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
An examination of Williams account of agent-regret leads to its supplementation, and to an explanation of why we are attached to, and responsible for, some of our actions even when we do not control ...
More
An examination of Williams account of agent-regret leads to its supplementation, and to an explanation of why we are attached to, and responsible for, some of our actions even when we do not control them, by relating our attachments to the emerging sense of who we are. These reflections lead to showing (a) that the control principle of responsibility reaches further than is often assumes, e.g. to establish responsibility for some beliefs and emotions, and (b) that we are responsible for actions regarding which the control principle does not apply. The chapter defends a rational functioning principle of responsibility. It concludes with some observations about how these conclusion bear on the question of blameworthiness which follow in Williams's footsteps.Less
An examination of Williams account of agent-regret leads to its supplementation, and to an explanation of why we are attached to, and responsible for, some of our actions even when we do not control them, by relating our attachments to the emerging sense of who we are. These reflections lead to showing (a) that the control principle of responsibility reaches further than is often assumes, e.g. to establish responsibility for some beliefs and emotions, and (b) that we are responsible for actions regarding which the control principle does not apply. The chapter defends a rational functioning principle of responsibility. It concludes with some observations about how these conclusion bear on the question of blameworthiness which follow in Williams's footsteps.
Martha Klein
- Published in print:
- 1990
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198248347
- eISBN:
- 9780191681134
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198248347.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
The arguments in Chapter 2 established that there is not an independent C-condition for blameworthiness (that is a C-condition which must be fulfilled in addition to the M-condition). Where does this ...
More
The arguments in Chapter 2 established that there is not an independent C-condition for blameworthiness (that is a C-condition which must be fulfilled in addition to the M-condition). Where does this leave the incompatibilist? He has been described as someone who assumes that there is an independent C-condition and whose commitment to such a condition is what motivates his incompatibilism. This chapter argues that his incompatibilism has not just been motivated by the belief in a C-condition; it has also been fuelled by the belief in ‘a U-condition for blameworthiness’— the condition that an agent's morally reprehensible decision or choice should not be caused by factors for which he is not responsible. The chapter shows that the commitment to a U-condition for blameworthiness is enough to motivate the belief that determinism and moral responsibility are incompatible. But it also suggests that the incompatibilist might have mistaken his commitment to a U-condition for a commitment to an independent C-condition for blameworthiness.Less
The arguments in Chapter 2 established that there is not an independent C-condition for blameworthiness (that is a C-condition which must be fulfilled in addition to the M-condition). Where does this leave the incompatibilist? He has been described as someone who assumes that there is an independent C-condition and whose commitment to such a condition is what motivates his incompatibilism. This chapter argues that his incompatibilism has not just been motivated by the belief in a C-condition; it has also been fuelled by the belief in ‘a U-condition for blameworthiness’— the condition that an agent's morally reprehensible decision or choice should not be caused by factors for which he is not responsible. The chapter shows that the commitment to a U-condition for blameworthiness is enough to motivate the belief that determinism and moral responsibility are incompatible. But it also suggests that the incompatibilist might have mistaken his commitment to a U-condition for a commitment to an independent C-condition for blameworthiness.
Martha Klein
- Published in print:
- 1990
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198248347
- eISBN:
- 9780191681134
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198248347.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter discusses the arguments for two claims: (1) that belief in the U-condition for blameworthiness is logically incoherent; and (2) that the U-condition cannot be fulfilled. The success of ...
More
This chapter discusses the arguments for two claims: (1) that belief in the U-condition for blameworthiness is logically incoherent; and (2) that the U-condition cannot be fulfilled. The success of arguments for the first claim would constitute a conclusive case for saying that we ought not to be committed to the U-condition. The success of arguments for the second claim would make it reasonable to ask whether we ought to be so committed. It is argued that there is no incoherence in the belief that fulfilment of the U-condition is necessary for blameworthiness, but that the U-condition for blameworthiness cannot be fulfilled.Less
This chapter discusses the arguments for two claims: (1) that belief in the U-condition for blameworthiness is logically incoherent; and (2) that the U-condition cannot be fulfilled. The success of arguments for the first claim would constitute a conclusive case for saying that we ought not to be committed to the U-condition. The success of arguments for the second claim would make it reasonable to ask whether we ought to be so committed. It is argued that there is no incoherence in the belief that fulfilment of the U-condition is necessary for blameworthiness, but that the U-condition for blameworthiness cannot be fulfilled.
Martha Klein
- Published in print:
- 1990
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198248347
- eISBN:
- 9780191681134
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198248347.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
It has been established that the U-condition for blameworthiness (probably) cannot be fulfilled. Our commitment to the belief in this condition is a consequence of our commitment to the belief that ...
More
It has been established that the U-condition for blameworthiness (probably) cannot be fulfilled. Our commitment to the belief in this condition is a consequence of our commitment to the belief that offenders who are motivated by states for which they are not responsible do not deserve to be blamed. It follows that if and when we blame people for flouting moral requirements we are doing something which is unjust. This chapter then addresses the question of whether we should give up blaming. It argues that to the extent that we have strong moral feelings about certain things, we would continue to feel intensely even if we fully acknowledged that no one deserved to be blamed or punished.Less
It has been established that the U-condition for blameworthiness (probably) cannot be fulfilled. Our commitment to the belief in this condition is a consequence of our commitment to the belief that offenders who are motivated by states for which they are not responsible do not deserve to be blamed. It follows that if and when we blame people for flouting moral requirements we are doing something which is unjust. This chapter then addresses the question of whether we should give up blaming. It argues that to the extent that we have strong moral feelings about certain things, we would continue to feel intensely even if we fully acknowledged that no one deserved to be blamed or punished.
Martha Klein
- Published in print:
- 1990
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198248347
- eISBN:
- 9780191681134
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198248347.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
Because we are committed to the U-condition for blameworthiness and because the U-condition cannot be fulfilled, we are forced to conclude that blaming is unjust. This makes things uncomfortable for ...
More
Because we are committed to the U-condition for blameworthiness and because the U-condition cannot be fulfilled, we are forced to conclude that blaming is unjust. This makes things uncomfortable for us since, for reasons discussed in Chapter 6, we are committed to blaming. This chapter argues that although this discomfort cannot be obliterated, but it might be possible to ease it. One way of easing it would be to accept that we are also committed to a compatibilist condition for blameworthiness whose fulfilment would preclude fulfilment of the U-condition.Less
Because we are committed to the U-condition for blameworthiness and because the U-condition cannot be fulfilled, we are forced to conclude that blaming is unjust. This makes things uncomfortable for us since, for reasons discussed in Chapter 6, we are committed to blaming. This chapter argues that although this discomfort cannot be obliterated, but it might be possible to ease it. One way of easing it would be to accept that we are also committed to a compatibilist condition for blameworthiness whose fulfilment would preclude fulfilment of the U-condition.
Robert Kane
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780195126563
- eISBN:
- 9780199868506
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195126564.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
It is argued on historical grounds that two criteria for free will have led people to suppose it must be incompatible with determinism. The first and most commonly discussed of these criteria is the ...
More
It is argued on historical grounds that two criteria for free will have led people to suppose it must be incompatible with determinism. The first and most commonly discussed of these criteria is the requirement of avoidability or “alternative possibilities” (AP) (that one who acts from free will must have the power to do otherwise or “could have done otherwise”). The second criterion is less commonly discussed, but I argue that it is the more important and central requirement for free will: “ultimate responsibility” (UR), being the ultimate originator or creator of one's own purposes, character, and achievements. This obscure, but pivotal, notion of ultimate responsibility, and the related notion of ultimate origination, are analyzed and their relation to the historical problem of free will is explained.Less
It is argued on historical grounds that two criteria for free will have led people to suppose it must be incompatible with determinism. The first and most commonly discussed of these criteria is the requirement of avoidability or “alternative possibilities” (AP) (that one who acts from free will must have the power to do otherwise or “could have done otherwise”). The second criterion is less commonly discussed, but I argue that it is the more important and central requirement for free will: “ultimate responsibility” (UR), being the ultimate originator or creator of one's own purposes, character, and achievements. This obscure, but pivotal, notion of ultimate responsibility, and the related notion of ultimate origination, are analyzed and their relation to the historical problem of free will is explained.
William MacAskill, Krister Bykvist, and Toby Ord
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- October 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198722274
- eISBN:
- 9780191789106
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198722274.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
We summarize the argument of the book: the case for taking moral uncertainty seriously, and the case for an information-sensitive account: the correct rule for making decisions under moral ...
More
We summarize the argument of the book: the case for taking moral uncertainty seriously, and the case for an information-sensitive account: the correct rule for making decisions under moral uncertainty depends crucially on the information provided by the moral theories in which one has credence. We then note some open questions that would require further work to address, such as how to axiomatize decision-making under moral uncertainty, how we should assign deontic statuses, such as permissible and impermissible, under moral uncertainty, and what a reasonable credence distribution across different moral theories looks like. We end by considering what implications our argument has for the value of doing moral philosophy, suggesting we should conclude that further normative research is one of the most important moral priorities of our time.Less
We summarize the argument of the book: the case for taking moral uncertainty seriously, and the case for an information-sensitive account: the correct rule for making decisions under moral uncertainty depends crucially on the information provided by the moral theories in which one has credence. We then note some open questions that would require further work to address, such as how to axiomatize decision-making under moral uncertainty, how we should assign deontic statuses, such as permissible and impermissible, under moral uncertainty, and what a reasonable credence distribution across different moral theories looks like. We end by considering what implications our argument has for the value of doing moral philosophy, suggesting we should conclude that further normative research is one of the most important moral priorities of our time.
Susan Sauvé Meyer
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- January 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199697427
- eISBN:
- 9780191732072
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199697427.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Ancient Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
This chapter considers Aristotle's own explanation of why he includes a discussion of voluntariness in his discussion of moral character. The connection he sees between voluntariness and the ...
More
This chapter considers Aristotle's own explanation of why he includes a discussion of voluntariness in his discussion of moral character. The connection he sees between voluntariness and the praiseworthiness and blameworthiness of states of character gives us reason to suppose that the account of voluntariness is intended to capture conditions of moral responsibility for action. He thinks we are morally responsible for those actions and feelings produced by our states of moral character. The account of praiseworthiness on which he relies, however, fails to endorse a common modern assumption about moral responsibility — the view that one's praiseworthiness or blameworthiness for action requires responsibility for the states of character from which one acts.Less
This chapter considers Aristotle's own explanation of why he includes a discussion of voluntariness in his discussion of moral character. The connection he sees between voluntariness and the praiseworthiness and blameworthiness of states of character gives us reason to suppose that the account of voluntariness is intended to capture conditions of moral responsibility for action. He thinks we are morally responsible for those actions and feelings produced by our states of moral character. The account of praiseworthiness on which he relies, however, fails to endorse a common modern assumption about moral responsibility — the view that one's praiseworthiness or blameworthiness for action requires responsibility for the states of character from which one acts.
ALAN NORRIE
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- January 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780198259565
- eISBN:
- 9780191710636
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198259565.003.0006
- Subject:
- Law, Comparative Law, Philosophy of Law
This chapter examines an alternative revisionist approach to criminal justice thinking by focusing on the work of Antony Duff. The Kantian problematic encourages both defensive rationalisation of a ...
More
This chapter examines an alternative revisionist approach to criminal justice thinking by focusing on the work of Antony Duff. The Kantian problematic encourages both defensive rationalisation of a morality of form and critical revision, which, seeking to move beyond the ‘mother position’, still remains tied to it. This is what characterises the three main moves in Duff's work, in his theory of punishment, his account of responsibility, and his analysis of legal culpability. The chapter begins with a discussion on the nature of revisionism in criminal justice thinking, then moves to a critique of Duff's views on blameworthiness, responsibility, and culpability. Duff's revisionist attempts to graft ‘contextual’ additions onto the Kantian framework, to make good its separations, are analysed. Duff develops a communitarian view of the blameworthy subject, a character view of the responsible subject, and a morally substantive view of the culpable subject. All three moves are invoked by the Kantian problematic of false separation.Less
This chapter examines an alternative revisionist approach to criminal justice thinking by focusing on the work of Antony Duff. The Kantian problematic encourages both defensive rationalisation of a morality of form and critical revision, which, seeking to move beyond the ‘mother position’, still remains tied to it. This is what characterises the three main moves in Duff's work, in his theory of punishment, his account of responsibility, and his analysis of legal culpability. The chapter begins with a discussion on the nature of revisionism in criminal justice thinking, then moves to a critique of Duff's views on blameworthiness, responsibility, and culpability. Duff's revisionist attempts to graft ‘contextual’ additions onto the Kantian framework, to make good its separations, are analysed. Duff develops a communitarian view of the blameworthy subject, a character view of the responsible subject, and a morally substantive view of the culpable subject. All three moves are invoked by the Kantian problematic of false separation.
Douglas W. Portmore
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- January 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199794539
- eISBN:
- 9780199919260
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199794539.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
The chapter argues, on the basis of a conceptual connection between wrongdoing and blameworthiness, that we should accept moral rationalism: the view that an agent can be morally required to perform ...
More
The chapter argues, on the basis of a conceptual connection between wrongdoing and blameworthiness, that we should accept moral rationalism: the view that an agent can be morally required to perform a given act only if she has decisive reason, all things considered, to perform that act. And it argues that although we should reject all traditional versions of act-consequentialism given moral rationalism and certain plausible assumptions about what agents have decisive reason to do, we should accept some version of act-consequentialism, for act-consequentialism is entailed by the conjunction of moral rationalism and a certain plausible conception of practical reasons—namely, the teleological conception of practical reasons. Lastly, it is argued that act-consequentialism is best construed as a theory that ranks outcomes, not according to their impersonal value, but according to how much reason the agent has to desire that each outcome obtains.Less
The chapter argues, on the basis of a conceptual connection between wrongdoing and blameworthiness, that we should accept moral rationalism: the view that an agent can be morally required to perform a given act only if she has decisive reason, all things considered, to perform that act. And it argues that although we should reject all traditional versions of act-consequentialism given moral rationalism and certain plausible assumptions about what agents have decisive reason to do, we should accept some version of act-consequentialism, for act-consequentialism is entailed by the conjunction of moral rationalism and a certain plausible conception of practical reasons—namely, the teleological conception of practical reasons. Lastly, it is argued that act-consequentialism is best construed as a theory that ranks outcomes, not according to their impersonal value, but according to how much reason the agent has to desire that each outcome obtains.
Douglas W. Portmore
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- January 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199693269
- eISBN:
- 9780191732058
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199693269.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Political Philosophy
This paper provides a presumptive argument in favor of moral rationalism: the view that agents can be morally required to do only what they have decisive reason to do, all things considered. The ...
More
This paper provides a presumptive argument in favor of moral rationalism: the view that agents can be morally required to do only what they have decisive reason to do, all things considered. The argument is based on the assumption that there is a conceptual connection between wrongdoing and blameworthiness. The paper argues that if we accept moral rationalism, we should reject all traditional versions of act-consequentialism (e.g., act-utilitarianism). It furthermore argues that the demandingness objection against traditional versions of act-consequentialism is best construed as a more general objection stemming from moral rationalism.Less
This paper provides a presumptive argument in favor of moral rationalism: the view that agents can be morally required to do only what they have decisive reason to do, all things considered. The argument is based on the assumption that there is a conceptual connection between wrongdoing and blameworthiness. The paper argues that if we accept moral rationalism, we should reject all traditional versions of act-consequentialism (e.g., act-utilitarianism). It furthermore argues that the demandingness objection against traditional versions of act-consequentialism is best construed as a more general objection stemming from moral rationalism.
Ishtiyaque Haji
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- January 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780190260774
- eISBN:
- 9780190260798
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190260774.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, General
This chapter argues that the first primary conclusion of this book—that our range of obligations is narrow—in conjunction with principles that associate obligation and being to blame, ratifies the ...
More
This chapter argues that the first primary conclusion of this book—that our range of obligations is narrow—in conjunction with principles that associate obligation and being to blame, ratifies the second primary conclusion—that we are blameworthy for perhaps far less than what many may plausibly believe. The chapter also proposes additional arguments having to do with the changeability of obligations over time to support this second conclusion. Finally, it is proposed that the reach of nonmoral blameworthiness—prudential blameworthiness, for instance—is reduced as well, and for the same sorts of reason for which moral blameworthiness is constrained.Less
This chapter argues that the first primary conclusion of this book—that our range of obligations is narrow—in conjunction with principles that associate obligation and being to blame, ratifies the second primary conclusion—that we are blameworthy for perhaps far less than what many may plausibly believe. The chapter also proposes additional arguments having to do with the changeability of obligations over time to support this second conclusion. Finally, it is proposed that the reach of nonmoral blameworthiness—prudential blameworthiness, for instance—is reduced as well, and for the same sorts of reason for which moral blameworthiness is constrained.
Manuel Vargas
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- January 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199697540
- eISBN:
- 9780191748851
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199697540.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter argues that agents can be justified in holding one another responsible, irrespective of whether anyone is a libertarian agent. The chapter begins by exploring and rejecting several ...
More
This chapter argues that agents can be justified in holding one another responsible, irrespective of whether anyone is a libertarian agent. The chapter begins by exploring and rejecting several familiar approaches for justifying responsibility-characteristic practices, such as P. F. Strawson’s account and the consequentialist approach in the work of Schlick and others. It then goes on to argue for a teleological account—the agency cultivation model—that makes use of some of the ideas in these rejected approaches, while also making use of the idea of a Reasons account of the sort gestured at in chapter 5. It concludes by showing how responsibility practices and norms can be justified, independent of appeal to libertarian forms of agency, without running afoul of the traditional objections to moral influence approaches.Less
This chapter argues that agents can be justified in holding one another responsible, irrespective of whether anyone is a libertarian agent. The chapter begins by exploring and rejecting several familiar approaches for justifying responsibility-characteristic practices, such as P. F. Strawson’s account and the consequentialist approach in the work of Schlick and others. It then goes on to argue for a teleological account—the agency cultivation model—that makes use of some of the ideas in these rejected approaches, while also making use of the idea of a Reasons account of the sort gestured at in chapter 5. It concludes by showing how responsibility practices and norms can be justified, independent of appeal to libertarian forms of agency, without running afoul of the traditional objections to moral influence approaches.
Manuel Vargas
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- January 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199697540
- eISBN:
- 9780191748851
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199697540.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter fills in the details of how the account handles blame and desert. The first part of the chapter focuses on exculpation, and the question of how the norms of responsibility (roughly, ...
More
This chapter fills in the details of how the account handles blame and desert. The first part of the chapter focuses on exculpation, and the question of how the norms of responsibility (roughly, norms characterizable in terms of quality of will) interact with the dynamic nature of moral considerations-responsive agency. A key idea that emerges is that moral ecology—or the way in which circumstances affect our dispositions to morally good and bad behavior—is important. The second part of the chapter concerns desert, and the basis on which it makes sense to regard people as deserving moralized praise and blame. The chapter argues that Pereboom’s notion of basic desert is to be rejected, but that a plausible account of desert is given by something called the social self-governance model of desert. This is a picture of desert on which responsible agents deserve reactions to their blameworthy actions because such reactions help aid agents in their self-governance in light of moral considerations.Less
This chapter fills in the details of how the account handles blame and desert. The first part of the chapter focuses on exculpation, and the question of how the norms of responsibility (roughly, norms characterizable in terms of quality of will) interact with the dynamic nature of moral considerations-responsive agency. A key idea that emerges is that moral ecology—or the way in which circumstances affect our dispositions to morally good and bad behavior—is important. The second part of the chapter concerns desert, and the basis on which it makes sense to regard people as deserving moralized praise and blame. The chapter argues that Pereboom’s notion of basic desert is to be rejected, but that a plausible account of desert is given by something called the social self-governance model of desert. This is a picture of desert on which responsible agents deserve reactions to their blameworthy actions because such reactions help aid agents in their self-governance in light of moral considerations.
Christian Von Bar
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780198298397
- eISBN:
- 9780191685439
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198298397.003.0003
- Subject:
- Law, EU Law
In addition to an individual's personal blameworthiness, other reasons, such as force majeure and unavoidability of circumstances, may also play a role in the occurrence of damages to another ...
More
In addition to an individual's personal blameworthiness, other reasons, such as force majeure and unavoidability of circumstances, may also play a role in the occurrence of damages to another individual's property and violations of their basic rights. Furthermore, these external factors will also influence the defendant's accountability for the aggravation of the said damages and the occurrence of acts of misdemeanour. This chapter discusses several scenarios that would determine an individual's level of culpability relating to legal violations that have been committed against another individual. The defendant's innocence and liability can be weighed based on liability for fault and strict liability. Moreover, the person's motive for performing a certain action or for opting for inaction will be accordingly classified as liability for intention or as liability for negligence. This chapter also covers liabilities and personal misconducts relating to motor vehicles, products, and activities that would impair the environment.Less
In addition to an individual's personal blameworthiness, other reasons, such as force majeure and unavoidability of circumstances, may also play a role in the occurrence of damages to another individual's property and violations of their basic rights. Furthermore, these external factors will also influence the defendant's accountability for the aggravation of the said damages and the occurrence of acts of misdemeanour. This chapter discusses several scenarios that would determine an individual's level of culpability relating to legal violations that have been committed against another individual. The defendant's innocence and liability can be weighed based on liability for fault and strict liability. Moreover, the person's motive for performing a certain action or for opting for inaction will be accordingly classified as liability for intention or as liability for negligence. This chapter also covers liabilities and personal misconducts relating to motor vehicles, products, and activities that would impair the environment.