Claire Colebrook
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780748622276
- eISBN:
- 9780748671663
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Edinburgh University Press
- DOI:
- 10.3366/edinburgh/9780748622276.001.0001
- Subject:
- Literature, Criticism/Theory
This book, a critique and overview of contemporary post-structuralist theory, explores the Kantian and phenomenological background of Derrida, Deleuze, Foucault and Irigaray, and raises some key ...
More
This book, a critique and overview of contemporary post-structuralist theory, explores the Kantian and phenomenological background of Derrida, Deleuze, Foucault and Irigaray, and raises some key questions and issues in critical theory. Is it still possible to sustain a transcendental critical project? How do such projects fare in the current terrain of cultural studies and anti-representationalism? The book contributes to ethical and critical theory; situates poststructuralism in its philosophical background and in the sustained problematic of the enlightenment; and offers a critique of various appeals made to a would-be post-metaphysical or post-human culture.Less
This book, a critique and overview of contemporary post-structuralist theory, explores the Kantian and phenomenological background of Derrida, Deleuze, Foucault and Irigaray, and raises some key questions and issues in critical theory. Is it still possible to sustain a transcendental critical project? How do such projects fare in the current terrain of cultural studies and anti-representationalism? The book contributes to ethical and critical theory; situates poststructuralism in its philosophical background and in the sustained problematic of the enlightenment; and offers a critique of various appeals made to a would-be post-metaphysical or post-human culture.
Stephen Neale
- Published in print:
- 2001
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780199247158
- eISBN:
- 9780191598081
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199247153.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Language
Introduces the criticisms put forward by philosophers such as Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty to the idea that one thing might represent another: that thoughts, utterances, and inscriptions are ...
More
Introduces the criticisms put forward by philosophers such as Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty to the idea that one thing might represent another: that thoughts, utterances, and inscriptions are said to have content by virtue of their power to represent reality; and that those that do the job accurately are true, they correspond to the facts, or mirror reality—they are representations of reality. The author then outlines the deductive proof that he will present in the book to show that Davidson's and Rorty's criticisms are unfounded. The content of the proof is based on the work of Kurt Gödel and W. V. Quine, and demonstrates conclusively that (i) any supposedly non‐truth‐functional operation must satisfy an exacting logical condition in order to avoid collapsing into a truth‐function, and (ii) any theory of facts, states of affairs, situations, or propositions must satisfy a corresponding condition if such entities are not to collapse into a unity. The three main sections of the chapter: examine the case against representations made by Davidson and Rorty, including Davidson's notorious argument against facts; discuss Rorty's critique of representational philosophy (his anti‐representationalism); and consider collapsing (or slingshot) arguments that discredit the existence of facts (and are used in the critique of the fact–representation distinction), as put forward by Gottlob Frege, and developed by Alonzo Church, Quine, Davidson, and Gödel. The last section of the chapter outlines the structure of the book.Less
Introduces the criticisms put forward by philosophers such as Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty to the idea that one thing might represent another: that thoughts, utterances, and inscriptions are said to have content by virtue of their power to represent reality; and that those that do the job accurately are true, they correspond to the facts, or mirror reality—they are representations of reality. The author then outlines the deductive proof that he will present in the book to show that Davidson's and Rorty's criticisms are unfounded. The content of the proof is based on the work of Kurt Gödel and W. V. Quine, and demonstrates conclusively that (i) any supposedly non‐truth‐functional operation must satisfy an exacting logical condition in order to avoid collapsing into a truth‐function, and (ii) any theory of facts, states of affairs, situations, or propositions must satisfy a corresponding condition if such entities are not to collapse into a unity. The three main sections of the chapter: examine the case against representations made by Davidson and Rorty, including Davidson's notorious argument against facts; discuss Rorty's critique of representational philosophy (his anti‐representationalism); and consider collapsing (or slingshot) arguments that discredit the existence of facts (and are used in the critique of the fact–representation distinction), as put forward by Gottlob Frege, and developed by Alonzo Church, Quine, Davidson, and Gödel. The last section of the chapter outlines the structure of the book.
Andreas Müller
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198754329
- eISBN:
- 9780191904189
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198754329.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
Some things are reasons for us to perform certain actions. That it will spare you great pain in the future, for example, is a reason for you to go to the dentist now, and that you are already late ...
More
Some things are reasons for us to perform certain actions. That it will spare you great pain in the future, for example, is a reason for you to go to the dentist now, and that you are already late for work is a reason for you not to read the next article in the morning paper. Why are such considerations reasons for or against certain actions? Constructivism offers an intriguing answer to this question. Its basic idea is often encapsulated in the slogan that reasons are not discovered but made by us. This book elaborates the constructivist idea into a fully fledged account of practical reasons, makes its theoretical commitments explicit, and defends it against some well-known objections. It begins with an examination of the distinctive role that reason judgements play in the process of practical reasoning. This provides the resources for an anti-representationalist conception of the nature of those judgements, according to which they are true, if they are true, not because they accurately represent certain normative facts, but because of their role in sound reasoning. On the resulting view, a consideration owes its status as a reason to the truth of the corresponding reason judgement and thus, ultimately, to the soundness of a certain episode of reasoning. Consequently, our practical reasons exhibit a kind of mind-dependence, but this does not force us to deny their objectivity.Less
Some things are reasons for us to perform certain actions. That it will spare you great pain in the future, for example, is a reason for you to go to the dentist now, and that you are already late for work is a reason for you not to read the next article in the morning paper. Why are such considerations reasons for or against certain actions? Constructivism offers an intriguing answer to this question. Its basic idea is often encapsulated in the slogan that reasons are not discovered but made by us. This book elaborates the constructivist idea into a fully fledged account of practical reasons, makes its theoretical commitments explicit, and defends it against some well-known objections. It begins with an examination of the distinctive role that reason judgements play in the process of practical reasoning. This provides the resources for an anti-representationalist conception of the nature of those judgements, according to which they are true, if they are true, not because they accurately represent certain normative facts, but because of their role in sound reasoning. On the resulting view, a consideration owes its status as a reason to the truth of the corresponding reason judgement and thus, ultimately, to the soundness of a certain episode of reasoning. Consequently, our practical reasons exhibit a kind of mind-dependence, but this does not force us to deny their objectivity.
Bence Nanay
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- January 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199695379
- eISBN:
- 9780191760747
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199695379.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
This chapter introduces the general approach followed in the rest of the book—the starting point for explaining the human mind is the simple mental processes that we share with animals: the ...
More
This chapter introduces the general approach followed in the rest of the book—the starting point for explaining the human mind is the simple mental processes that we share with animals: the perceptual guidance of actions. This mental process is described with the help of the concept of “pragmatic representations”—perceptual representations that represent those features of objects that are relevant for the performance of an action. This approach is distinguished from the two most influential contemporary ways of thinking about the human mind: computationalism/propositionalism (according to which beliefs, desires or other propositional attitudes mediate between sensory input and motor output), and anti-representationalism/enactivism (according to which nothing mediates between sensory input and motor output—they form one intertwined dynamic process). According to the picture explored in this book, there are some special kind of representation, “pragmatic representations”, that (sometimes directly) mediate between sensory input and motor output.Less
This chapter introduces the general approach followed in the rest of the book—the starting point for explaining the human mind is the simple mental processes that we share with animals: the perceptual guidance of actions. This mental process is described with the help of the concept of “pragmatic representations”—perceptual representations that represent those features of objects that are relevant for the performance of an action. This approach is distinguished from the two most influential contemporary ways of thinking about the human mind: computationalism/propositionalism (according to which beliefs, desires or other propositional attitudes mediate between sensory input and motor output), and anti-representationalism/enactivism (according to which nothing mediates between sensory input and motor output—they form one intertwined dynamic process). According to the picture explored in this book, there are some special kind of representation, “pragmatic representations”, that (sometimes directly) mediate between sensory input and motor output.
Anandi Hattiangadi
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- September 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780198722199
- eISBN:
- 9780191789045
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198722199.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Language, Aesthetics
In his recent book, Meaning and Normativity, Allan Gibbard argues at length that meta-ethical expressivism can be profitably extended to semantic and intentional language: meta-linguistic discourse ...
More
In his recent book, Meaning and Normativity, Allan Gibbard argues at length that meta-ethical expressivism can be profitably extended to semantic and intentional language: meta-linguistic discourse about meaning, reference, content, and the like. This chapter argues that the extension of expressivism to semantic discourse is unprofitable and—worse still—in a certain sense self-undermining. It is unprofitable because it sheds no light on the problem of intentionality; and it undermines itself because many of the sentences that make up the expressivist’s theory are semantic sentences, and if these are understood to express non-cognitive attitudes of some kind, the expressivist’s explanations are spurious.Less
In his recent book, Meaning and Normativity, Allan Gibbard argues at length that meta-ethical expressivism can be profitably extended to semantic and intentional language: meta-linguistic discourse about meaning, reference, content, and the like. This chapter argues that the extension of expressivism to semantic discourse is unprofitable and—worse still—in a certain sense self-undermining. It is unprofitable because it sheds no light on the problem of intentionality; and it undermines itself because many of the sentences that make up the expressivist’s theory are semantic sentences, and if these are understood to express non-cognitive attitudes of some kind, the expressivist’s explanations are spurious.
Andreas Müller
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198754329
- eISBN:
- 9780191904189
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198754329.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This chapter argues that the Normative Guidance Account of practical reasoning defended in Chapter 2 provides constructivists with the resources to formulate an anti-representationalist account of ...
More
This chapter argues that the Normative Guidance Account of practical reasoning defended in Chapter 2 provides constructivists with the resources to formulate an anti-representationalist account of reason judgements. According to this account, these judgements are mental states whose characteristic cognitive function is to guide our reasoning, rather than to represent certain facts. The chapter also introduces a distinction between this rationalist version of anti-representationalism, which characterizes reason judgements in terms of their role in reasoning, and conativist versions of anti-representationalism, which characterize these judgements as motivational states. This is where the constructivist’s account of reason judgements differs from the one endorsed by most expressivists.Less
This chapter argues that the Normative Guidance Account of practical reasoning defended in Chapter 2 provides constructivists with the resources to formulate an anti-representationalist account of reason judgements. According to this account, these judgements are mental states whose characteristic cognitive function is to guide our reasoning, rather than to represent certain facts. The chapter also introduces a distinction between this rationalist version of anti-representationalism, which characterizes reason judgements in terms of their role in reasoning, and conativist versions of anti-representationalism, which characterize these judgements as motivational states. This is where the constructivist’s account of reason judgements differs from the one endorsed by most expressivists.
Bence Nanay
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- December 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199756018
- eISBN:
- 9780199395255
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199756018.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
The aim of this chapter is to raise some serious worries about anti-representationalism: the recently popular view according to which there are no perceptual representations. There are two very ...
More
The aim of this chapter is to raise some serious worries about anti-representationalism: the recently popular view according to which there are no perceptual representations. There are two very different ways of thinking about perception. According to representationalism, perceptual states are representations: they represent the world as being a certain way. They have content, which may or may not be different from the content of beliefs. They represent objects as having properties, sometimes veridically, sometimes not. According to anti-representationalism (which comes in various forms, as relationalism or as enactivism), perceptual states are not representations. Although anti-representationalism is more and more popular, the chapter argues that there are strong empirical reasons for mistrusting it. More specifically, it argues that it is inconsistent with some important empirical findings about dorsal perception and about the multimodality of perception.Less
The aim of this chapter is to raise some serious worries about anti-representationalism: the recently popular view according to which there are no perceptual representations. There are two very different ways of thinking about perception. According to representationalism, perceptual states are representations: they represent the world as being a certain way. They have content, which may or may not be different from the content of beliefs. They represent objects as having properties, sometimes veridically, sometimes not. According to anti-representationalism (which comes in various forms, as relationalism or as enactivism), perceptual states are not representations. Although anti-representationalism is more and more popular, the chapter argues that there are strong empirical reasons for mistrusting it. More specifically, it argues that it is inconsistent with some important empirical findings about dorsal perception and about the multimodality of perception.
Albert Newen and Gottfried Vosgerau
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- June 2021
- ISBN:
- 9780190686673
- eISBN:
- 9780190686703
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780190686673.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, Metaphysics/Epistemology
If we want to account for mental representations (MRs) as being used in scientific explanations and realized by neural correlates in biological systems, then we have to give up the traditional ...
More
If we want to account for mental representations (MRs) as being used in scientific explanations and realized by neural correlates in biological systems, then we have to give up the traditional Fodorian view of rigid symbolic MRs. However, we do not have to throw out the baby with the bathwater and accept anti-representationalism. Instead this chapter offers a new account of mental representations as real, nonstable, use-dependent, and situated. As such, they can be pivotal constituents of scientific explanations. The chapter demonstrates the empirical adequacy of this account by discussing cases of birds and rats relying on what-where-when memory. It argues that we need to involve nonlinguistic MRs to adequately account for their abilities. In this way, the alternative theory presented here provides a detailed description of situated mental representations: it combines a functionalist account of MR with a relational dimension that can vary with the situation type and that allows for nonstatic constructions of MRs in specific contexts.Less
If we want to account for mental representations (MRs) as being used in scientific explanations and realized by neural correlates in biological systems, then we have to give up the traditional Fodorian view of rigid symbolic MRs. However, we do not have to throw out the baby with the bathwater and accept anti-representationalism. Instead this chapter offers a new account of mental representations as real, nonstable, use-dependent, and situated. As such, they can be pivotal constituents of scientific explanations. The chapter demonstrates the empirical adequacy of this account by discussing cases of birds and rats relying on what-where-when memory. It argues that we need to involve nonlinguistic MRs to adequately account for their abilities. In this way, the alternative theory presented here provides a detailed description of situated mental representations: it combines a functionalist account of MR with a relational dimension that can vary with the situation type and that allows for nonstatic constructions of MRs in specific contexts.