P. Kyle Stanford
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- May 2006
- ISBN:
- 9780195174083
- eISBN:
- 9780199786367
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195174089.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science
The incredible achievements of modern scientific theories lead most of us to embrace scientific realism: the view that our best theories offer us at least roughly accurate descriptions of otherwise ...
More
The incredible achievements of modern scientific theories lead most of us to embrace scientific realism: the view that our best theories offer us at least roughly accurate descriptions of otherwise inaccessible parts of the world like genes, atoms, and the big bang. This book argues that careful attention to the history of scientific investigation invites a challenge to this view that is not well represented in contemporary debates about the nature of the scientific enterprise. The historical record of scientific inquiry, the book suggests, is characterized by the problem of unconceived alternatives. Past scientists have routinely failed even to conceive of alternatives to their own theories and lines of theoretical investigation, alternatives that were both well-confirmed by the evidence available at the time and sufficiently serious as to be ultimately accepted by later scientific communities. The book supports this claim with a detailed investigation of the mid-to-late 19th-century theories of inheritance and generation proposed in turn by Charles Darwin, Francis Galton, and August Weismann. It goes on to argue that this historical pattern strongly suggests that there are equally well-confirmed and scientifically serious alternatives to our own best theories that remain currently unconceived. Moreover, this challenge is more serious than those rooted in either the so-called pessimistic induction or the underdetermination of theories by evidence, in part because existing realist responses to these latter challenges offer no relief from the problem of unconceived alternatives itself.Less
The incredible achievements of modern scientific theories lead most of us to embrace scientific realism: the view that our best theories offer us at least roughly accurate descriptions of otherwise inaccessible parts of the world like genes, atoms, and the big bang. This book argues that careful attention to the history of scientific investigation invites a challenge to this view that is not well represented in contemporary debates about the nature of the scientific enterprise. The historical record of scientific inquiry, the book suggests, is characterized by the problem of unconceived alternatives. Past scientists have routinely failed even to conceive of alternatives to their own theories and lines of theoretical investigation, alternatives that were both well-confirmed by the evidence available at the time and sufficiently serious as to be ultimately accepted by later scientific communities. The book supports this claim with a detailed investigation of the mid-to-late 19th-century theories of inheritance and generation proposed in turn by Charles Darwin, Francis Galton, and August Weismann. It goes on to argue that this historical pattern strongly suggests that there are equally well-confirmed and scientifically serious alternatives to our own best theories that remain currently unconceived. Moreover, this challenge is more serious than those rooted in either the so-called pessimistic induction or the underdetermination of theories by evidence, in part because existing realist responses to these latter challenges offer no relief from the problem of unconceived alternatives itself.
P. Kyle Stanford
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- May 2006
- ISBN:
- 9780195174083
- eISBN:
- 9780199786367
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195174089.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science
This chapter focuses on August Weismann's theory of the germ-plasm. It is argued that both Weismann's failure to conceive of any alternative to the disintegration of the idioplasm as the mechanism of ...
More
This chapter focuses on August Weismann's theory of the germ-plasm. It is argued that both Weismann's failure to conceive of any alternative to the disintegration of the idioplasm as the mechanism of ontogenetic differentiation and nuclear control, and his failure to conceive of any genuinely facultative capacity on the part of the germ-plasm suggest that Weismann never conceived of the quite general possibility that the germ-plasm could itself serve as what we might call a productive rather than an expendable resource for the cell and/or the organism.Less
This chapter focuses on August Weismann's theory of the germ-plasm. It is argued that both Weismann's failure to conceive of any alternative to the disintegration of the idioplasm as the mechanism of ontogenetic differentiation and nuclear control, and his failure to conceive of any genuinely facultative capacity on the part of the germ-plasm suggest that Weismann never conceived of the quite general possibility that the germ-plasm could itself serve as what we might call a productive rather than an expendable resource for the cell and/or the organism.
Jan Sapp
- Published in print:
- 2003
- Published Online:
- September 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780195156195
- eISBN:
- 9780199790340
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195156195.003.0008
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
This chapter discusses how cell theory revolutionized the concept of the individual. A plant or an animal was no longer conceived of as a singular entity constructed out of cellular tissue. What was ...
More
This chapter discusses how cell theory revolutionized the concept of the individual. A plant or an animal was no longer conceived of as a singular entity constructed out of cellular tissue. What was important was that the cell was alive — it possessed all the attributes of life. The cell state, dawn of protistology, the term “cell” as a misnomer, and the theory formulated by the Freiburg zoologist August Weismann are discussed.Less
This chapter discusses how cell theory revolutionized the concept of the individual. A plant or an animal was no longer conceived of as a singular entity constructed out of cellular tissue. What was important was that the cell was alive — it possessed all the attributes of life. The cell state, dawn of protistology, the term “cell” as a misnomer, and the theory formulated by the Freiburg zoologist August Weismann are discussed.
Cicely Saunders
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- November 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198570530
- eISBN:
- 9780191730412
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198570530.003.0022
- Subject:
- Palliative Care, Palliative Medicine Research
The year 1978 saw the publication of the textbook which, over a long period, so many had been encouraging Cicely Saunders and her colleagues to produce. In this chapter, she opens up a discussion on ...
More
The year 1978 saw the publication of the textbook which, over a long period, so many had been encouraging Cicely Saunders and her colleagues to produce. In this chapter, she opens up a discussion on the relationship of terminal care to the ‘cure’ and ‘care’ systems. However it is also noted that ‘no patient should become locked in what is for him the wrong system’. The discussion outlines a broad definition of terminal care, drawing on the work of Weismann — an absence of suffering, preservation of important relationships, an interval for anticipatory grief, relief of remaining conflicts, belief in timeliness, exercise of feasible options and activities, and consistency with physical limitations, all within the scope of one's ego ideal.Less
The year 1978 saw the publication of the textbook which, over a long period, so many had been encouraging Cicely Saunders and her colleagues to produce. In this chapter, she opens up a discussion on the relationship of terminal care to the ‘cure’ and ‘care’ systems. However it is also noted that ‘no patient should become locked in what is for him the wrong system’. The discussion outlines a broad definition of terminal care, drawing on the work of Weismann — an absence of suffering, preservation of important relationships, an interval for anticipatory grief, relief of remaining conflicts, belief in timeliness, exercise of feasible options and activities, and consistency with physical limitations, all within the scope of one's ego ideal.
Johannes Fabian
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- May 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780520221222
- eISBN:
- 9780520923935
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of California Press
- DOI:
- 10.1525/california/9780520221222.003.0007
- Subject:
- Anthropology, African Cultural Anthropology
Many discoveries entertained European readers, fed the greed for power and wealth of many nations, and made explorers famous. This chapter presents one discovery that was absent from ancient myths ...
More
Many discoveries entertained European readers, fed the greed for power and wealth of many nations, and made explorers famous. This chapter presents one discovery that was absent from ancient myths and contemporary projects of exploration. The celebrated first European crossing of the continent from west to east by Pogge and Wissmann (in the end by Wissmann alone) and the founding of what became a strategic post for the Congo Free State (Luluaburg) hinged on the discovery of the bene diamba, “the children of hemp,” who lived in the land of lubuku, “friendship,” or moyo, “life.” The long-term effects of Pogge's and Wissman's association with the Bashilange have been fateful. In short, they set up one of the most conflict-ridden ethnic categorizations and divisions in colonial and postcolonial times: Between the Lulua and the Baluba Kasai.Less
Many discoveries entertained European readers, fed the greed for power and wealth of many nations, and made explorers famous. This chapter presents one discovery that was absent from ancient myths and contemporary projects of exploration. The celebrated first European crossing of the continent from west to east by Pogge and Wissmann (in the end by Wissmann alone) and the founding of what became a strategic post for the Congo Free State (Luluaburg) hinged on the discovery of the bene diamba, “the children of hemp,” who lived in the land of lubuku, “friendship,” or moyo, “life.” The long-term effects of Pogge's and Wissman's association with the Bashilange have been fateful. In short, they set up one of the most conflict-ridden ethnic categorizations and divisions in colonial and postcolonial times: Between the Lulua and the Baluba Kasai.
Trevor Pearce
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- May 2021
- ISBN:
- 9780226719887
- eISBN:
- 9780226720081
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226720081.003.0006
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
This chapter examines how both first- and second-cohort pragmatists participated in the debates over the causal factors of evolution that accompanied the reception of August Weismann’s work in the ...
More
This chapter examines how both first- and second-cohort pragmatists participated in the debates over the causal factors of evolution that accompanied the reception of August Weismann’s work in the 1890s. Weismann, a biologist, argued in the mid-1880s that the hereditary substance was confined to what he called the “germ-plasm,” which was isolated from the rest of the body. One implication was that acquired characteristics could not be inherited, undermining the neo-Lamarckian theories of American scientists such as Edward Drinker Cope and Henry Fairfield Osborn. These discussions were of interest to William James and Charles Sanders Peirce because of their opposition to Herbert Spencer (also a neo-Lamarckian) and Peirce’s 1893 essay “Evolutionary Love” should be interpreted as contributing to the factors of evolution debates. John Dewey also followed these debates, applying key concepts from an 1893–95 dispute between Spencer and Weismann to his early work in ethics and social psychology.Less
This chapter examines how both first- and second-cohort pragmatists participated in the debates over the causal factors of evolution that accompanied the reception of August Weismann’s work in the 1890s. Weismann, a biologist, argued in the mid-1880s that the hereditary substance was confined to what he called the “germ-plasm,” which was isolated from the rest of the body. One implication was that acquired characteristics could not be inherited, undermining the neo-Lamarckian theories of American scientists such as Edward Drinker Cope and Henry Fairfield Osborn. These discussions were of interest to William James and Charles Sanders Peirce because of their opposition to Herbert Spencer (also a neo-Lamarckian) and Peirce’s 1893 essay “Evolutionary Love” should be interpreted as contributing to the factors of evolution debates. John Dewey also followed these debates, applying key concepts from an 1893–95 dispute between Spencer and Weismann to his early work in ethics and social psychology.
Brian Bix
- Published in print:
- 1995
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780198260509
- eISBN:
- 9780191682100
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198260509.003.0002
- Subject:
- Law, Philosophy of Law
Both Hart and Weismann wrote on the existence of ‘open texture’ within the circumstantial gaps of human-flawed rules and practical perception. Weismann derived the term from his approach to ...
More
Both Hart and Weismann wrote on the existence of ‘open texture’ within the circumstantial gaps of human-flawed rules and practical perception. Weismann derived the term from his approach to Wittgenstein's philosophy, and argued on the general vagueness of the language. H.L.A. Hart argued on judicial interpretation between formalism and rule-scepticism that legal rules have an applicable meaning in accordance with the depending situation, but the problem lies within the language vagueness in interpreted application. The chapter discusses Hart's view on the nature of language, rules and rule application.Less
Both Hart and Weismann wrote on the existence of ‘open texture’ within the circumstantial gaps of human-flawed rules and practical perception. Weismann derived the term from his approach to Wittgenstein's philosophy, and argued on the general vagueness of the language. H.L.A. Hart argued on judicial interpretation between formalism and rule-scepticism that legal rules have an applicable meaning in accordance with the depending situation, but the problem lies within the language vagueness in interpreted application. The chapter discusses Hart's view on the nature of language, rules and rule application.
Piers J. Hale
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- January 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780226108490
- eISBN:
- 9780226108520
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226108520.001.0001
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
Historians know that Darwin was influenced by the political economist Thomas Malthus and that natural selection was therefore compatible with Whig industrial politics, but Political Descent shows ...
More
Historians know that Darwin was influenced by the political economist Thomas Malthus and that natural selection was therefore compatible with Whig industrial politics, but Political Descent shows that the earlier Lamarckian ideas that were popular among radicals persisted throughout the nineteenth century both alongside and in opposition to various forms of Malthusian Darwinism. After 1832 English radicalism split along class lines; Whig radicals embraced Malthus in justification of competitive individualism whereas working class radicals favoured anti-Malthusian and Lamarckian evolutionary ideas. Thus there were two traditions of evolutionary political thought in nineteenth-century England. Political Descent traces their respective development up to the First World War. Although many Whigs interpreted natural selection as an endorsement of economic competition, the outspoken Lamarckian Herbert Spencer remained ambivalent about Malthus. Rather than endorsing individualism, in Descent of Man Darwin explained the evolution of genuinely other-regarding morals through both inter-group and intra group selective pressures. This was indicative of a broader move away from laissez-faire to a collectivist ‘new liberalism’, Thomas Huxley debated this issue with Spencer. While liberals embraced collective solutions to the social consequences of industrialisation, others drew socialist conclusions, prompting the socialist revival of the 1880s and 1890s. Political Descent charts diverse liberal and socialist politics that were variously built around Malthusian or anti-Malthusian interpretations of evolution, culminating in a consideration of the problems that August Weismann's work on heredity raised for the Lamarckian aspirations of many socialists. Further, Weismann's theory of ‘panmixia’ exacerbated late-nineteenth and early twentieth-century concerns about evolutionary degeneration.Less
Historians know that Darwin was influenced by the political economist Thomas Malthus and that natural selection was therefore compatible with Whig industrial politics, but Political Descent shows that the earlier Lamarckian ideas that were popular among radicals persisted throughout the nineteenth century both alongside and in opposition to various forms of Malthusian Darwinism. After 1832 English radicalism split along class lines; Whig radicals embraced Malthus in justification of competitive individualism whereas working class radicals favoured anti-Malthusian and Lamarckian evolutionary ideas. Thus there were two traditions of evolutionary political thought in nineteenth-century England. Political Descent traces their respective development up to the First World War. Although many Whigs interpreted natural selection as an endorsement of economic competition, the outspoken Lamarckian Herbert Spencer remained ambivalent about Malthus. Rather than endorsing individualism, in Descent of Man Darwin explained the evolution of genuinely other-regarding morals through both inter-group and intra group selective pressures. This was indicative of a broader move away from laissez-faire to a collectivist ‘new liberalism’, Thomas Huxley debated this issue with Spencer. While liberals embraced collective solutions to the social consequences of industrialisation, others drew socialist conclusions, prompting the socialist revival of the 1880s and 1890s. Political Descent charts diverse liberal and socialist politics that were variously built around Malthusian or anti-Malthusian interpretations of evolution, culminating in a consideration of the problems that August Weismann's work on heredity raised for the Lamarckian aspirations of many socialists. Further, Weismann's theory of ‘panmixia’ exacerbated late-nineteenth and early twentieth-century concerns about evolutionary degeneration.
Emily Herring
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- June 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780190490447
- eISBN:
- 9780190490478
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190490447.003.0017
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, before Wilhelm Johannsen first distinguished between the hidden hereditary makeup of organisms (the genotype) and its macroscopic manifestations (the ...
More
In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, before Wilhelm Johannsen first distinguished between the hidden hereditary makeup of organisms (the genotype) and its macroscopic manifestations (the phenotype), theories postulating invisible internal particles meant to account for the external appearance of living organisms were devised. These were not just attempts at solving the problems of inheritance and generation, but also a way of addressing the intimate nature of the bodies of living beings. The problem of embodiment was—for naturalists such as Buffon, Darwin, and Weismann—the problem of understanding how the macroscopic level could be explained by the activity of the microscopic particular level. By the time Johannsen had coined the term “gene” in 1909 this problem had shifted into working out how organisms’ visible characters could explain the workings of the particles hidden within. This Reflection retraces the transition from one conception of embodiment to the other.Less
In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, before Wilhelm Johannsen first distinguished between the hidden hereditary makeup of organisms (the genotype) and its macroscopic manifestations (the phenotype), theories postulating invisible internal particles meant to account for the external appearance of living organisms were devised. These were not just attempts at solving the problems of inheritance and generation, but also a way of addressing the intimate nature of the bodies of living beings. The problem of embodiment was—for naturalists such as Buffon, Darwin, and Weismann—the problem of understanding how the macroscopic level could be explained by the activity of the microscopic particular level. By the time Johannsen had coined the term “gene” in 1909 this problem had shifted into working out how organisms’ visible characters could explain the workings of the particles hidden within. This Reflection retraces the transition from one conception of embodiment to the other.
Piers J. Hale
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- January 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780226108490
- eISBN:
- 9780226108520
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226108520.003.0006
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
This chapter focuses on the ways British socialists interpreted evolution. As Fabianism and Marxism became more prominent, the Lamarkian and anti-Malthusian politics of men like William Morris and ...
More
This chapter focuses on the ways British socialists interpreted evolution. As Fabianism and Marxism became more prominent, the Lamarkian and anti-Malthusian politics of men like William Morris and Peter Kropotkin became increasingly marginalized. H.G. Wells, a one-time admirer of Morris and sometime Fabian, took particular exception to Morris's anti-Malthusian assumptions. This became all the more so in light of his conviction that the German cell biologist August Weismann had undermined Lamarckian inheritance. Without the inheritance of acquired characters any hope of a significant human evolution on a relevant time scale was lost. Further, Wells became convinced that Weismann's theory of panmixia further undermined Morris's vision of socialism. Any ‘epoch of rest’ that ameliorated selective pressure would cause biological degeneration. George Bernard Shaw, was as Malthusian as Wells, but intervened to oppose Wells'sWeismannism. An ardent Lamarckian Shaw ultimately reflected that Morris might have been right.Less
This chapter focuses on the ways British socialists interpreted evolution. As Fabianism and Marxism became more prominent, the Lamarkian and anti-Malthusian politics of men like William Morris and Peter Kropotkin became increasingly marginalized. H.G. Wells, a one-time admirer of Morris and sometime Fabian, took particular exception to Morris's anti-Malthusian assumptions. This became all the more so in light of his conviction that the German cell biologist August Weismann had undermined Lamarckian inheritance. Without the inheritance of acquired characters any hope of a significant human evolution on a relevant time scale was lost. Further, Wells became convinced that Weismann's theory of panmixia further undermined Morris's vision of socialism. Any ‘epoch of rest’ that ameliorated selective pressure would cause biological degeneration. George Bernard Shaw, was as Malthusian as Wells, but intervened to oppose Wells'sWeismannism. An ardent Lamarckian Shaw ultimately reflected that Morris might have been right.
Piers J. Hale
- Published in print:
- 2014
- Published Online:
- January 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780226108490
- eISBN:
- 9780226108520
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226108520.003.0007
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
Political Descent closes with a consideration of the young socialist statistician, Karl Pearson. Pearson debated the extent to which Weismann's views had implications for socialist politics. In the ...
More
Political Descent closes with a consideration of the young socialist statistician, Karl Pearson. Pearson debated the extent to which Weismann's views had implications for socialist politics. In the pages of Nature as well as in more popular journals he rejected the views of the popular author, Benjamin Kidd, who had repeated the argument that Weismann undermined socialism in his bestselling Social Evolution. Even though Pearson eventually came to accept Weismann's views, he argued that a combination of eugenics at home and an imperialist foreign policy would maintain a sufficiently Malthusian struggle to prevent national degeneration. The onset of the Great War of 1914 is a logical place to bring this history to a close. It was in the wake of the horrors of the First World War that Darwinian arguments went out of favor in British political circles, even though they were picked up again in later years.Less
Political Descent closes with a consideration of the young socialist statistician, Karl Pearson. Pearson debated the extent to which Weismann's views had implications for socialist politics. In the pages of Nature as well as in more popular journals he rejected the views of the popular author, Benjamin Kidd, who had repeated the argument that Weismann undermined socialism in his bestselling Social Evolution. Even though Pearson eventually came to accept Weismann's views, he argued that a combination of eugenics at home and an imperialist foreign policy would maintain a sufficiently Malthusian struggle to prevent national degeneration. The onset of the Great War of 1914 is a logical place to bring this history to a close. It was in the wake of the horrors of the First World War that Darwinian arguments went out of favor in British political circles, even though they were picked up again in later years.
Edward J. Larson
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- March 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780226608402
- eISBN:
- 9780226608426
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226608426.003.0008
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
In the late 1800s, Charles Darwin and other naturalists supported a blending view of inheritance whereby offspring possess a middling mix of their parents' traits. Many of these naturalists also ...
More
In the late 1800s, Charles Darwin and other naturalists supported a blending view of inheritance whereby offspring possess a middling mix of their parents' traits. Many of these naturalists also argued that individuals pass at least some of their acquired characteristics to their descendants. Darwin proposed that acquired characteristics and other environmentally induced changes in a parent's hereditary material (which he called “gemmules”) account in large part for the inheritable variations that drove evolution. Inspired by the evolutionary theories of his first cousin, Darwin, Francis Galton developed hereditarian notions that helped to lay the foundation for both genetics and eugenics. Eugenics was endorsed by evolutionary geneticists such as August Weismann, Karl Pearson, W. F. R. Weldon, William Bateson, and Hugo de Vries, which, as a result, gave it enormous scientific credibility in America and Europe. This chapter explores the role of biology in the emergence of the eugenics movement in the Anglo-Saxon world.Less
In the late 1800s, Charles Darwin and other naturalists supported a blending view of inheritance whereby offspring possess a middling mix of their parents' traits. Many of these naturalists also argued that individuals pass at least some of their acquired characteristics to their descendants. Darwin proposed that acquired characteristics and other environmentally induced changes in a parent's hereditary material (which he called “gemmules”) account in large part for the inheritable variations that drove evolution. Inspired by the evolutionary theories of his first cousin, Darwin, Francis Galton developed hereditarian notions that helped to lay the foundation for both genetics and eugenics. Eugenics was endorsed by evolutionary geneticists such as August Weismann, Karl Pearson, W. F. R. Weldon, William Bateson, and Hugo de Vries, which, as a result, gave it enormous scientific credibility in America and Europe. This chapter explores the role of biology in the emergence of the eugenics movement in the Anglo-Saxon world.
Sander Gliboff
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- August 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780262072939
- eISBN:
- 9780262273923
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- The MIT Press
- DOI:
- 10.7551/mitpress/9780262072939.003.0072
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
This book has examined the texts, the translation process, and especially the intellectual context in which Charles Darwin’s On the Origin of Species was written and interpreted. The result is a very ...
More
This book has examined the texts, the translation process, and especially the intellectual context in which Charles Darwin’s On the Origin of Species was written and interpreted. The result is a very different picture, not only of Heinrich Georg Bronn and Ernst Haeckel but also of the older morphology with which they were associated. This new picture of Haeckel has implications for our understanding of later developments in evolution and evolutionary thought and sheds new light on his conflicts over “mechanistic” and experimental approaches to embryology, particularly with Wilhelm His or Wilhelm Roux, and with August Weismann. Haeckel’s dispute with Weismann to define and defend Darwinism persisted into the twentieth century.Less
This book has examined the texts, the translation process, and especially the intellectual context in which Charles Darwin’s On the Origin of Species was written and interpreted. The result is a very different picture, not only of Heinrich Georg Bronn and Ernst Haeckel but also of the older morphology with which they were associated. This new picture of Haeckel has implications for our understanding of later developments in evolution and evolutionary thought and sheds new light on his conflicts over “mechanistic” and experimental approaches to embryology, particularly with Wilhelm His or Wilhelm Roux, and with August Weismann. Haeckel’s dispute with Weismann to define and defend Darwinism persisted into the twentieth century.
David A. West
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- January 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780813062600
- eISBN:
- 9780813051581
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University Press of Florida
- DOI:
- 10.5744/florida/9780813062600.003.0004
- Subject:
- Society and Culture, Latin American Studies
In reaction to Darwin’s On theOrigin of Species, which he read in October 1861, Müller reorganized his ongoing research on crustacea. One result was his Für Darwin, published in 1864, utilizing ...
More
In reaction to Darwin’s On theOrigin of Species, which he read in October 1861, Müller reorganized his ongoing research on crustacea. One result was his Für Darwin, published in 1864, utilizing detailed crustacean research. Müller applied Darwin’s theory of natural selection to crustaceans, yielding some novel predictions, some of which he subsequently verified. Müller showed that crustacean embryology provided a partial guide to crustacean genealogy, demonstrated that genealogical thinking resolved puzzles in the chaotic taxonomy of crustaceans, defended Darwin’s theory against several common objections, and demonstrated its superiority to special creationist alternatives. Darwin responded to Für Darwin with high praise and instigated an English translation of the book. He initiated correspondence with Müller, in which they discussed applications and extensions of Darwin’s theories and directions for further fieldwork. Für Darwin initially drew a generally tepid reception, with severe reviews from some critics. The chapter closes by comparing Müller’s evaluations of Darwin’s theory with those of Ernst Haeckel and August Weismann.Less
In reaction to Darwin’s On theOrigin of Species, which he read in October 1861, Müller reorganized his ongoing research on crustacea. One result was his Für Darwin, published in 1864, utilizing detailed crustacean research. Müller applied Darwin’s theory of natural selection to crustaceans, yielding some novel predictions, some of which he subsequently verified. Müller showed that crustacean embryology provided a partial guide to crustacean genealogy, demonstrated that genealogical thinking resolved puzzles in the chaotic taxonomy of crustaceans, defended Darwin’s theory against several common objections, and demonstrated its superiority to special creationist alternatives. Darwin responded to Für Darwin with high praise and instigated an English translation of the book. He initiated correspondence with Müller, in which they discussed applications and extensions of Darwin’s theories and directions for further fieldwork. Für Darwin initially drew a generally tepid reception, with severe reviews from some critics. The chapter closes by comparing Müller’s evaluations of Darwin’s theory with those of Ernst Haeckel and August Weismann.
David A. West
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- January 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780813062600
- eISBN:
- 9780813051581
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University Press of Florida
- DOI:
- 10.5744/florida/9780813062600.003.0010
- Subject:
- Society and Culture, Latin American Studies
Müller received Darwin’s Power of Movement in Plants in 1881. In response, he sent Darwin new evidence for universal nutational movement in plants and some functions it served. In 1883 Müller’s ...
More
Müller received Darwin’s Power of Movement in Plants in 1881. In response, he sent Darwin new evidence for universal nutational movement in plants and some functions it served. In 1883 Müller’s younger half brother, Wilhelm, joined Fritz for two years, working primarily on larval butterflies, their food plants, and their phylogeny. Wilhelm’s letters home describe Fritz and Caroline’s family life. Starting in 1885, correspondence with August Weismann explored the continuity of the germplasm. Weismann’s account implied that novel characteristics can only be generated by sexual mixing of germplasms with one exception: unicellular organisms have no separate somatic cells. Therefore, environmental change could yield inheritance of acquired characteristics. Müller denied this restriction. Continuity of the germplasm does not guarantee its constancy nor block novel heritable variations. Indeed, asexually propagating plants inherit novel variations, even when the variation originated in differentiated somatic cells: buds or runners occasionally transmit novel heritable characters to their offspring.Less
Müller received Darwin’s Power of Movement in Plants in 1881. In response, he sent Darwin new evidence for universal nutational movement in plants and some functions it served. In 1883 Müller’s younger half brother, Wilhelm, joined Fritz for two years, working primarily on larval butterflies, their food plants, and their phylogeny. Wilhelm’s letters home describe Fritz and Caroline’s family life. Starting in 1885, correspondence with August Weismann explored the continuity of the germplasm. Weismann’s account implied that novel characteristics can only be generated by sexual mixing of germplasms with one exception: unicellular organisms have no separate somatic cells. Therefore, environmental change could yield inheritance of acquired characteristics. Müller denied this restriction. Continuity of the germplasm does not guarantee its constancy nor block novel heritable variations. Indeed, asexually propagating plants inherit novel variations, even when the variation originated in differentiated somatic cells: buds or runners occasionally transmit novel heritable characters to their offspring.
Adam Wilkins
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- August 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780262015141
- eISBN:
- 9780262295642
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- The MIT Press
- DOI:
- 10.7551/mitpress/9780262015141.003.0013
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
This chapter presents three important reasons why evolutionary biologists dismissed Lamarckism or soft inheritance from the Modern Synthesis. The first is the legacy of adhering to August Weismann's ...
More
This chapter presents three important reasons why evolutionary biologists dismissed Lamarckism or soft inheritance from the Modern Synthesis. The first is the legacy of adhering to August Weismann's ideas of the separation of germ line and soma. The second is the absence, from the 1920s through the 1940s, of convincing for strong evidence for the inheritance of acquired characteristics. The third reason came from the assumptions of population and quantitative genetics, which were developing at the time.Less
This chapter presents three important reasons why evolutionary biologists dismissed Lamarckism or soft inheritance from the Modern Synthesis. The first is the legacy of adhering to August Weismann's ideas of the separation of germ line and soma. The second is the absence, from the 1920s through the 1940s, of convincing for strong evidence for the inheritance of acquired characteristics. The third reason came from the assumptions of population and quantitative genetics, which were developing at the time.