Robert A. Skipper and Michael R. Dietrich
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- December 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199595372
- eISBN:
- 9780191774799
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199595372.003.0002
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
Sewall Wright's 1932 adaptive landscape diagram is the most influential visual heuristic in evolutionary biology. Yet, the diagram has met with criticism from biologists and philosophers since its ...
More
Sewall Wright's 1932 adaptive landscape diagram is the most influential visual heuristic in evolutionary biology. Yet, the diagram has met with criticism from biologists and philosophers since its origination. This chapter states that the diagram is a valuable evaluation heuristic for assessing the dynamical behaviour of population genetics models. Although Wright's particular use of it is of dubious value, other biologists have established the diagram's positive heuristic value for evaluating dynamical behaviour. This chapter surveys some of the most influential biological and philosophical work considering the role of the adaptive landscape in evolutionary biology. The chapter builds on a distinction between models, metaphors, and diagrams to make a case for why adaptive landscapes as diagrams have heuristic value for evolutionary biologists.Less
Sewall Wright's 1932 adaptive landscape diagram is the most influential visual heuristic in evolutionary biology. Yet, the diagram has met with criticism from biologists and philosophers since its origination. This chapter states that the diagram is a valuable evaluation heuristic for assessing the dynamical behaviour of population genetics models. Although Wright's particular use of it is of dubious value, other biologists have established the diagram's positive heuristic value for evaluating dynamical behaviour. This chapter surveys some of the most influential biological and philosophical work considering the role of the adaptive landscape in evolutionary biology. The chapter builds on a distinction between models, metaphors, and diagrams to make a case for why adaptive landscapes as diagrams have heuristic value for evolutionary biologists.
Michael R. Dietrich and Robert A. Skipper
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- December 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199595372
- eISBN:
- 9780191774799
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199595372.003.0001
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
This chapter traces the origins and conceptual lineages of the adaptive landscape concept and its representations. While Armand Janet's 1895 concept arguably marks the origin of the adaptive ...
More
This chapter traces the origins and conceptual lineages of the adaptive landscape concept and its representations. While Armand Janet's 1895 concept arguably marks the origin of the adaptive landscape concept and even its graphic representation, Janet's concept had very limited impact when compared to Sewall Wright's concept from 1932. As part of his effort to reconcile Mendelian genetics and Darwinian evolution in his shifting balance theory, Wright offered the metaphor of the adaptive landscape and its topographic representation as a way of depicting the effect of variations in population size, migration, and the strength of selection. Wright's genetic version of the adaptive landscape inspired other versions of the adaptive landscape based on phenotypic changes and on molecular changes. As a result, the history of the adaptive landscape is described in terms of three lineages based on the material basis of the adaptive landscape: the genetic landscape, the phenotypic landscape, and the molecular landscape.Less
This chapter traces the origins and conceptual lineages of the adaptive landscape concept and its representations. While Armand Janet's 1895 concept arguably marks the origin of the adaptive landscape concept and even its graphic representation, Janet's concept had very limited impact when compared to Sewall Wright's concept from 1932. As part of his effort to reconcile Mendelian genetics and Darwinian evolution in his shifting balance theory, Wright offered the metaphor of the adaptive landscape and its topographic representation as a way of depicting the effect of variations in population size, migration, and the strength of selection. Wright's genetic version of the adaptive landscape inspired other versions of the adaptive landscape based on phenotypic changes and on molecular changes. As a result, the history of the adaptive landscape is described in terms of three lineages based on the material basis of the adaptive landscape: the genetic landscape, the phenotypic landscape, and the molecular landscape.
Erik I Svensson and Ryan Caisbeek
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- December 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199595372
- eISBN:
- 9780191774799
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199595372.003.0019
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
Sewall Wright’s classic Adaptive Landscape has been a highly successful metaphor and scientific concept in evolutionary biology. It has influenced many different research subdisciplines in ...
More
Sewall Wright’s classic Adaptive Landscape has been a highly successful metaphor and scientific concept in evolutionary biology. It has influenced many different research subdisciplines in evolutionary biology and inspired generations of researchers, even though it has also sparked deep scientific and philosophical controversies. Among such subdisciplines are population genetics, evolutionary ecology, quantitative genetics, experimental evolution, conservation biology, speciation and macroevolutionary dynamics, mimicry, saltational evolution, behavioural ecology, molecular biology, protein networks, and theoretical studies on development.Less
Sewall Wright’s classic Adaptive Landscape has been a highly successful metaphor and scientific concept in evolutionary biology. It has influenced many different research subdisciplines in evolutionary biology and inspired generations of researchers, even though it has also sparked deep scientific and philosophical controversies. Among such subdisciplines are population genetics, evolutionary ecology, quantitative genetics, experimental evolution, conservation biology, speciation and macroevolutionary dynamics, mimicry, saltational evolution, behavioural ecology, molecular biology, protein networks, and theoretical studies on development.
John O. Reiss
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780520258938
- eISBN:
- 9780520944404
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of California Press
- DOI:
- 10.1525/california/9780520258938.003.0007
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
Darwin's separation between adaptedness and existence entered into modern evolutionary theory at its root, in the population genetics work of Sewall Wright and J. B. S. Haldane. This chapter shows ...
More
Darwin's separation between adaptedness and existence entered into modern evolutionary theory at its root, in the population genetics work of Sewall Wright and J. B. S. Haldane. This chapter shows how the teleological aspect of Darwin's theory was translated into the mathematical language of population genetics, particularly by Sewall Wright. This teleology is exemplified by Wright's metaphor of the adaptive landscape; it is absent from R. A. Fisher's fundamental theorem. The chapter also examines the debate over genetic load, showing that the separation of adaptedness from existence is transferred to the mathematical theory most directly in the form of confusion between absolute and relative fitness.Less
Darwin's separation between adaptedness and existence entered into modern evolutionary theory at its root, in the population genetics work of Sewall Wright and J. B. S. Haldane. This chapter shows how the teleological aspect of Darwin's theory was translated into the mathematical language of population genetics, particularly by Sewall Wright. This teleology is exemplified by Wright's metaphor of the adaptive landscape; it is absent from R. A. Fisher's fundamental theorem. The chapter also examines the debate over genetic load, showing that the separation of adaptedness from existence is transferred to the mathematical theory most directly in the form of confusion between absolute and relative fitness.
Massimo Pigliucci
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- December 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199595372
- eISBN:
- 9780191774799
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199595372.003.0003
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
The adaptive landscape metaphor is one of the most persistent in evolutionary biology, and has generated much theoretical debate (if far less empirical investigation). This chapter briefly traces ...
More
The adaptive landscape metaphor is one of the most persistent in evolutionary biology, and has generated much theoretical debate (if far less empirical investigation). This chapter briefly traces the history of the concept since its introduction by Sewall Wright in the 1930s. It then distinguishes four types of landscapes pertinent to evolutionary theory: fitness landscapes, adaptive landscapes, fitness surfaces, and morphospaces. These are more or less loosely related to each other, and sometimes the relationship is complex and difficult to explore empirically. The chapter argues that some versions of the landscape metaphor have lost their utility and should be replaced by more sophisticated metaphors, or abandoned altogether. It suggests that — somewhat surprisingly — the most useful type of landscape may turn out to be the morphospace, a concept that allows for a productive bridge between theoretical analyses and empirical results, especially in fields such as palaeontology and evolutionary developmental biology. In particular, the chapter discusses examples from the paleontological literature that constitute instances of truly (and stunningly) predictive theoretical analysis in what is often considered an entirely descriptive historical science.Less
The adaptive landscape metaphor is one of the most persistent in evolutionary biology, and has generated much theoretical debate (if far less empirical investigation). This chapter briefly traces the history of the concept since its introduction by Sewall Wright in the 1930s. It then distinguishes four types of landscapes pertinent to evolutionary theory: fitness landscapes, adaptive landscapes, fitness surfaces, and morphospaces. These are more or less loosely related to each other, and sometimes the relationship is complex and difficult to explore empirically. The chapter argues that some versions of the landscape metaphor have lost their utility and should be replaced by more sophisticated metaphors, or abandoned altogether. It suggests that — somewhat surprisingly — the most useful type of landscape may turn out to be the morphospace, a concept that allows for a productive bridge between theoretical analyses and empirical results, especially in fields such as palaeontology and evolutionary developmental biology. In particular, the chapter discusses examples from the paleontological literature that constitute instances of truly (and stunningly) predictive theoretical analysis in what is often considered an entirely descriptive historical science.
Michael J. Wade
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- January 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780226129563
- eISBN:
- 9780226129877
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226129877.003.0009
- Subject:
- Biology, Evolutionary Biology / Genetics
This chapter contains a discussion of the ecological and the genetic basis for Sewall Wright’s Shifting Balance Theory. It also relays discussions of the author with Wright about how to ...
More
This chapter contains a discussion of the ecological and the genetic basis for Sewall Wright’s Shifting Balance Theory. It also relays discussions of the author with Wright about how to experimentally test his theory using flour beetle metapopulations. The experimental design used by Wade and C. J. Goodnight to test Wright’s theory and to estimate realized group heritabilities is illustrated. The surprizing finding that interdemic selection every-other generation produced a larger response than selection at every generation was interpreted as evidence of non-additive effects on population mean fitness.Less
This chapter contains a discussion of the ecological and the genetic basis for Sewall Wright’s Shifting Balance Theory. It also relays discussions of the author with Wright about how to experimentally test his theory using flour beetle metapopulations. The experimental design used by Wade and C. J. Goodnight to test Wright’s theory and to estimate realized group heritabilities is illustrated. The surprizing finding that interdemic selection every-other generation produced a larger response than selection at every generation was interpreted as evidence of non-additive effects on population mean fitness.
Samir Okasha
- Published in print:
- 2018
- Published Online:
- July 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780198815082
- eISBN:
- 9780191852909
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198815082.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind
Fitness maximization, or optimization, is a controversial idea in evolutionary biology. One classical formulation of this idea is that natural selection will tend to push a population up a peak in an ...
More
Fitness maximization, or optimization, is a controversial idea in evolutionary biology. One classical formulation of this idea is that natural selection will tend to push a population up a peak in an adaptive landscape, as Sewall Wright first proposed. However, the hill-climbing property only obtains under particular conditions, and even then the ascent is not usually by the steepest route; this shows why it is misleading to assimilate the process of natural selection to a process of goal-directed choice. A different formulation of the idea of fitness-maximization is R. A. Fisher’s ‘fundamental theorem of natural selection’. However, the theorem points only to a weak sense in which selection is an optimizing process, for it requires that ‘environmental constancy’ be understood in a highly specific way. It does not vindicate the claim that natural selection has an intrinsic tendency to produce adaptation.Less
Fitness maximization, or optimization, is a controversial idea in evolutionary biology. One classical formulation of this idea is that natural selection will tend to push a population up a peak in an adaptive landscape, as Sewall Wright first proposed. However, the hill-climbing property only obtains under particular conditions, and even then the ascent is not usually by the steepest route; this shows why it is misleading to assimilate the process of natural selection to a process of goal-directed choice. A different formulation of the idea of fitness-maximization is R. A. Fisher’s ‘fundamental theorem of natural selection’. However, the theorem points only to a weak sense in which selection is an optimizing process, for it requires that ‘environmental constancy’ be understood in a highly specific way. It does not vindicate the claim that natural selection has an intrinsic tendency to produce adaptation.
Garrett Hardin
- Published in print:
- 1993
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780195078114
- eISBN:
- 9780197560716
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780195078114.003.0030
- Subject:
- Earth Sciences and Geography, Economic Geography
In 1956 an association of lay Catholics in Europe announced an international essay contest, the object of which was to find a solution to overpopulation in the underdeveloped nations. The solution, ...
More
In 1956 an association of lay Catholics in Europe announced an international essay contest, the object of which was to find a solution to overpopulation in the underdeveloped nations. The solution, they said, would "have to comply with the requirements of Catholic principles and at the same time must be effective from a positive point of view." In words plainer than the proposers were willing to use: the solution must not resort to abortion, sterilization, or contraception. A substantial prize awaited the winner. Four years later the committee announced that no entry had been found worthy of the prize: the contest was now closed. "After a number of entries had been eliminated because they did not satisfy the material conditions laid down in the rules, five manuscripts remained to be judged. Four of these had to be considered as not dealing with the question as formulated." The fifth entry, the committee decided, presented "no real solution." From this failure the committee extracted the following moral: what was required was team research. "When the fundamental problems of modern science require highly coordinated team work based on carefully planned programmes, it cannot be expected that the fundamental world-wide problems of those branches of science dealing with human beings and society would be solved by individual endeavours." The committee's statement sounds very open-minded; but is their analysis sound? Suppose a contest had the following objective: To find two different odd integers lying between the numbers 7 and 9. What good would it do to appoint a multidisciplinary committee to work on that problem? None. The very method of stating the problem ensures that it has no solution in the real world. Our knowledge of human behavior is not as securely based as our knowledge of mathematics, but the gap between the two is not overwhelming. Natural selection rewards the kind of human behavior that mocks the ideals of the Roman Catholic Church. In a community that cherishes the lives of all fetuses and children, how can functional sterility, whether partial (continence) or total (celibacy) be selected for? More than thirty years have passed since this call for an interdisciplinary committee to work on a Catholic solution, but the committee has apparently never been formed. Who would serve on it? Don Quixote, perhaps; who else?
Less
In 1956 an association of lay Catholics in Europe announced an international essay contest, the object of which was to find a solution to overpopulation in the underdeveloped nations. The solution, they said, would "have to comply with the requirements of Catholic principles and at the same time must be effective from a positive point of view." In words plainer than the proposers were willing to use: the solution must not resort to abortion, sterilization, or contraception. A substantial prize awaited the winner. Four years later the committee announced that no entry had been found worthy of the prize: the contest was now closed. "After a number of entries had been eliminated because they did not satisfy the material conditions laid down in the rules, five manuscripts remained to be judged. Four of these had to be considered as not dealing with the question as formulated." The fifth entry, the committee decided, presented "no real solution." From this failure the committee extracted the following moral: what was required was team research. "When the fundamental problems of modern science require highly coordinated team work based on carefully planned programmes, it cannot be expected that the fundamental world-wide problems of those branches of science dealing with human beings and society would be solved by individual endeavours." The committee's statement sounds very open-minded; but is their analysis sound? Suppose a contest had the following objective: To find two different odd integers lying between the numbers 7 and 9. What good would it do to appoint a multidisciplinary committee to work on that problem? None. The very method of stating the problem ensures that it has no solution in the real world. Our knowledge of human behavior is not as securely based as our knowledge of mathematics, but the gap between the two is not overwhelming. Natural selection rewards the kind of human behavior that mocks the ideals of the Roman Catholic Church. In a community that cherishes the lives of all fetuses and children, how can functional sterility, whether partial (continence) or total (celibacy) be selected for? More than thirty years have passed since this call for an interdisciplinary committee to work on a Catholic solution, but the committee has apparently never been formed. Who would serve on it? Don Quixote, perhaps; who else?