Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
If the philosophy of history is now in a flourishing state in English-speaking countries and in countries where English is read, this is due in no small measure to the stimulus provided by the ...
More
If the philosophy of history is now in a flourishing state in English-speaking countries and in countries where English is read, this is due in no small measure to the stimulus provided by the writings of R. G. Collingwood. Much of the best work that has been done in this field since the posthumous publication in 1946 of his well-known book The Idea of History has been a conscious attempt to develop or to emend views which he expressed; and much of the rest has owed a good deal of its interest to its connection with those views. The extent to which Collingwood pioneered the subject in British philosophy is suggested by his own efforts in The Idea of History to name his British predecessors. This book presents a systematic critical examination of Collingwood's whole philosophy of history, focusing on his well-known contention that history is, or should be, a re-enactment of past experience or a re-thinking of past thought.Less
If the philosophy of history is now in a flourishing state in English-speaking countries and in countries where English is read, this is due in no small measure to the stimulus provided by the writings of R. G. Collingwood. Much of the best work that has been done in this field since the posthumous publication in 1946 of his well-known book The Idea of History has been a conscious attempt to develop or to emend views which he expressed; and much of the rest has owed a good deal of its interest to its connection with those views. The extent to which Collingwood pioneered the subject in British philosophy is suggested by his own efforts in The Idea of History to name his British predecessors. This book presents a systematic critical examination of Collingwood's whole philosophy of history, focusing on his well-known contention that history is, or should be, a re-enactment of past experience or a re-thinking of past thought.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter examines some other things which R. G. Collingwood had to say which have at times been interpreted as denying the objectivity of history. These include his claim that historians' ...
More
This chapter examines some other things which R. G. Collingwood had to say which have at times been interpreted as denying the objectivity of history. These include his claim that historians' conclusions are necessarily expressions of their own points of view, that what history offers is thus a view of the past from a present perspective, and that it can therefore be expected to be continually rewritten. His views on the nature of narrative in history are also considered. It is argued that nothing which Collingwood says about history being relative to a point of view justifies describing him as a sceptic. However, taking historical relativism to mean that the knowledge claimed by historians is conditioned by their points of view, Collingwood appeared to be an historical relativist. Collingwood's perspectivism often takes the more specific form of maintaining that what historians offer is accounts of the past from a present point of view. This chapter also discusses retrospective historical understanding, as well as presentism, retrospectivity, reality, and anachronism in Collingwood's theory of re-enactment.Less
This chapter examines some other things which R. G. Collingwood had to say which have at times been interpreted as denying the objectivity of history. These include his claim that historians' conclusions are necessarily expressions of their own points of view, that what history offers is thus a view of the past from a present perspective, and that it can therefore be expected to be continually rewritten. His views on the nature of narrative in history are also considered. It is argued that nothing which Collingwood says about history being relative to a point of view justifies describing him as a sceptic. However, taking historical relativism to mean that the knowledge claimed by historians is conditioned by their points of view, Collingwood appeared to be an historical relativist. Collingwood's perspectivism often takes the more specific form of maintaining that what historians offer is accounts of the past from a present point of view. This chapter also discusses retrospective historical understanding, as well as presentism, retrospectivity, reality, and anachronism in Collingwood's theory of re-enactment.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter examines some things which R. G. Collingwood had to say about what he saw as paradigmatic cases of re-enactment: cases in which the past actions of particular individuals are understood ...
More
This chapter examines some things which R. G. Collingwood had to say about what he saw as paradigmatic cases of re-enactment: cases in which the past actions of particular individuals are understood in terms of what the person concerned thought about his situation. Collingwood's chief claims in such cases are analysed and sometimes rephrased in language which he does not himself use but which will be more familiar to many readers. The first task is to set out in a little detail what Collingwood means when he insists that historical understanding requires a re-enactment of past experience or a re-thinking of past thought. As noted already, commentators have differed about the importance of this idea for his whole theory of historical inquiry. But there have also been disagreements about the viability, and even the coherence, of the idea itself.Less
This chapter examines some things which R. G. Collingwood had to say about what he saw as paradigmatic cases of re-enactment: cases in which the past actions of particular individuals are understood in terms of what the person concerned thought about his situation. Collingwood's chief claims in such cases are analysed and sometimes rephrased in language which he does not himself use but which will be more familiar to many readers. The first task is to set out in a little detail what Collingwood means when he insists that historical understanding requires a re-enactment of past experience or a re-thinking of past thought. As noted already, commentators have differed about the importance of this idea for his whole theory of historical inquiry. But there have also been disagreements about the viability, and even the coherence, of the idea itself.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter examines the kind of understanding which R. G. Collingwood himself more often contrasted with the re-enactive sort: understanding achieved through scientific explanation, or explanation ...
More
This chapter examines the kind of understanding which R. G. Collingwood himself more often contrasted with the re-enactive sort: understanding achieved through scientific explanation, or explanation in terms of laws. Two views of re-enactive explanation itself are considered, along with some implications of Collingwood's theory for some related questions concerning re-enactment, such as the viability of assuming determinism in history and the extent to which historians properly use generalisations. Collingwood's ‘scientific’ theory of explanation is also sometimes known as the ‘nomological’ or ‘law-subsumption’ theory. The fact that Collingwood at least sometimes represents re-enactive explanation as logically excluding nomological explanation of the same thing raises the general question of where he stands on the issue of historical determinism.Less
This chapter examines the kind of understanding which R. G. Collingwood himself more often contrasted with the re-enactive sort: understanding achieved through scientific explanation, or explanation in terms of laws. Two views of re-enactive explanation itself are considered, along with some implications of Collingwood's theory for some related questions concerning re-enactment, such as the viability of assuming determinism in history and the extent to which historians properly use generalisations. Collingwood's ‘scientific’ theory of explanation is also sometimes known as the ‘nomological’ or ‘law-subsumption’ theory. The fact that Collingwood at least sometimes represents re-enactive explanation as logically excluding nomological explanation of the same thing raises the general question of where he stands on the issue of historical determinism.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter examines a Collingwoodian doctrine which has often been seen as closely related to that of re-enactment: the claim that historical inquiry requires an exercise of the historian's ...
More
This chapter examines a Collingwoodian doctrine which has often been seen as closely related to that of re-enactment: the claim that historical inquiry requires an exercise of the historian's imagination. Critics of R. G. Collingwood have often associated these two ideas, and some have claimed that his notion that historical thinking requires imagination seems to reflect all too well certain weaknesses which they find in his work as an historian. An analysis of Collingwood's conception of the historical imagination will lead to a consideration of his contention that, besides requiring on the empirical side, the identification and interpretation of evidence, historical thinking has an important a priori dimension. Collingwood's idea of historical continuity, coherence, and necessity is discussed, along with the sense in which he thinks historians deal with individuality, the extent to which he sees synthesis as well as analysis as involved in historical understanding, and his position on periodisation and on the need for universal history.Less
This chapter examines a Collingwoodian doctrine which has often been seen as closely related to that of re-enactment: the claim that historical inquiry requires an exercise of the historian's imagination. Critics of R. G. Collingwood have often associated these two ideas, and some have claimed that his notion that historical thinking requires imagination seems to reflect all too well certain weaknesses which they find in his work as an historian. An analysis of Collingwood's conception of the historical imagination will lead to a consideration of his contention that, besides requiring on the empirical side, the identification and interpretation of evidence, historical thinking has an important a priori dimension. Collingwood's idea of historical continuity, coherence, and necessity is discussed, along with the sense in which he thinks historians deal with individuality, the extent to which he sees synthesis as well as analysis as involved in historical understanding, and his position on periodisation and on the need for universal history.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter examines the question of whether R. G. Collingwood's theory of historical understanding is generally applicable to an historical subject-matter. Even those who have found much to admire ...
More
This chapter examines the question of whether R. G. Collingwood's theory of historical understanding is generally applicable to an historical subject-matter. Even those who have found much to admire in Collingwood's Idea of History and related writings have often complained that his idea of re-enactment is relevant only to a small part of what is normally regarded as history. Collingwood's theory of understanding has been charged with being too intellectualistic, too rationalistic, too action-oriented, too mentalistic, and too individualistic, to be regarded as an acceptable general account of the nature of historical understanding. This chapter first discusses the scope of re-enactment, then Collingwood's supposed intellectualism, rationality in Collingwood's subject-matter of history, his exclusion of perception, appetite, and emotion from the proper subject-matter of history, and how the idea of re-enactment can apply to the history of art and metaphysics.Less
This chapter examines the question of whether R. G. Collingwood's theory of historical understanding is generally applicable to an historical subject-matter. Even those who have found much to admire in Collingwood's Idea of History and related writings have often complained that his idea of re-enactment is relevant only to a small part of what is normally regarded as history. Collingwood's theory of understanding has been charged with being too intellectualistic, too rationalistic, too action-oriented, too mentalistic, and too individualistic, to be regarded as an acceptable general account of the nature of historical understanding. This chapter first discusses the scope of re-enactment, then Collingwood's supposed intellectualism, rationality in Collingwood's subject-matter of history, his exclusion of perception, appetite, and emotion from the proper subject-matter of history, and how the idea of re-enactment can apply to the history of art and metaphysics.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
R. G. Collingwood has also been accused, because of the way he emphasises the historian's concern with past ‘thought’, of ignoring the considerable role played by physical conditions in history, and ...
More
R. G. Collingwood has also been accused, because of the way he emphasises the historian's concern with past ‘thought’, of ignoring the considerable role played by physical conditions in history, and of remaining strangely silent about how large-scale social processes are to be understood. This chapter looks at the kinds of difficulties which are often thought to be raised by Collingwood's allegedly ignoring the role played by ‘objective conditions’ in history. These objective conditions refer to the natural environment in which people lived and acted, and the social groups to which they belonged, or which were in some way relevant to their lives. This chapter examines what Collingwood says about the place of physical conditions in history as well as his view of the role of social conditions, events, and structures.Less
R. G. Collingwood has also been accused, because of the way he emphasises the historian's concern with past ‘thought’, of ignoring the considerable role played by physical conditions in history, and of remaining strangely silent about how large-scale social processes are to be understood. This chapter looks at the kinds of difficulties which are often thought to be raised by Collingwood's allegedly ignoring the role played by ‘objective conditions’ in history. These objective conditions refer to the natural environment in which people lived and acted, and the social groups to which they belonged, or which were in some way relevant to their lives. This chapter examines what Collingwood says about the place of physical conditions in history as well as his view of the role of social conditions, events, and structures.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter explores how far R. G. Collingwood holds that the investigations of historians, so conceived, are capable of attaining objective truth about the past; whether, on his view, historians ...
More
This chapter explores how far R. G. Collingwood holds that the investigations of historians, so conceived, are capable of attaining objective truth about the past; whether, on his view, historians can reasonably claim to recover the past ‘as it actually was’, or whether their conclusions must be considered subjective, or relativist, or, in some other damaging sense, non-objective. Collingwood himself, although claiming to have repudiated the philosophical realism in which he was reared, denied that he was to be considered an idealist. This chapter argues that Collingwood was not an idealist, and that his view of re-enactment as historical understanding as re-enactment is, by implication, objectivist. It also analyses historical scepticism, constructionism, and anti-constructionism in his re-enactment doctrine.Less
This chapter explores how far R. G. Collingwood holds that the investigations of historians, so conceived, are capable of attaining objective truth about the past; whether, on his view, historians can reasonably claim to recover the past ‘as it actually was’, or whether their conclusions must be considered subjective, or relativist, or, in some other damaging sense, non-objective. Collingwood himself, although claiming to have repudiated the philosophical realism in which he was reared, denied that he was to be considered an idealist. This chapter argues that Collingwood was not an idealist, and that his view of re-enactment as historical understanding as re-enactment is, by implication, objectivist. It also analyses historical scepticism, constructionism, and anti-constructionism in his re-enactment doctrine.
Dray William H.
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This epilogue summarises what has emerged with regard to both R. G. Collingwood's view of the nature of historical understanding as re-enactment, and the place which that doctrine should occupy in a ...
More
This epilogue summarises what has emerged with regard to both R. G. Collingwood's view of the nature of historical understanding as re-enactment, and the place which that doctrine should occupy in a broader Collingwoodian theory of historical understanding. The nature of Collingwood's theory of re-enactment has been explored, along with its limits and its relation to some other ideas which play, or are thought to play, a legitimate role in historical thinking. Collingwood's idea of re-enactive understanding has been discussed, and the idea that re-enactive explanation might simply be an incomplete form of scientific explanation has been noted and rejected. Two other Collingwoodian ideas which have been treated at some length are the idea of an a priori historical imagination and Collingwood's doctrine of the ideality of the past.Less
This epilogue summarises what has emerged with regard to both R. G. Collingwood's view of the nature of historical understanding as re-enactment, and the place which that doctrine should occupy in a broader Collingwoodian theory of historical understanding. The nature of Collingwood's theory of re-enactment has been explored, along with its limits and its relation to some other ideas which play, or are thought to play, a legitimate role in historical thinking. Collingwood's idea of re-enactive understanding has been discussed, and the idea that re-enactive explanation might simply be an incomplete form of scientific explanation has been noted and rejected. Two other Collingwoodian ideas which have been treated at some length are the idea of an a priori historical imagination and Collingwood's doctrine of the ideality of the past.
Richard Hingley
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- January 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199641413
- eISBN:
- 9780191745720
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199641413.003.0012
- Subject:
- Classical Studies, Archaeology: Classical
This chapter explores a programme of archaeological research conducted from the last decade of the nineteenth century to the 1940s. This work explored the date of construction, identity, and ...
More
This chapter explores a programme of archaeological research conducted from the last decade of the nineteenth century to the 1940s. This work explored the date of construction, identity, and signature of these frontier works, by addressing the location, form, and sequence of the individual features of the frontier. R. G. Collingwood, one of the most influential archaeologists involved in this work, defined ‘The period of scientific excavation’ in his important article ‘Hadrian's Wall: A History of the Problem’, arguing that it commenced in 1891 and lasted until his own time. The chapter examines Collingwood's claim that archaeological studies of the Wall had become more professional and scientific. It also considers the extent to which the great era of excavation resulted in a philosophy of thought that has damaged subsequent research on the Wall.Less
This chapter explores a programme of archaeological research conducted from the last decade of the nineteenth century to the 1940s. This work explored the date of construction, identity, and signature of these frontier works, by addressing the location, form, and sequence of the individual features of the frontier. R. G. Collingwood, one of the most influential archaeologists involved in this work, defined ‘The period of scientific excavation’ in his important article ‘Hadrian's Wall: A History of the Problem’, arguing that it commenced in 1891 and lasted until his own time. The chapter examines Collingwood's claim that archaeological studies of the Wall had become more professional and scientific. It also considers the extent to which the great era of excavation resulted in a philosophy of thought that has damaged subsequent research on the Wall.
William H. Dray
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198238812
- eISBN:
- 9780191679780
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198238812.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
A central motif of R. G. Collingwood's philosophy of history is the idea that historical understanding requires a re-enactment of past experience. However, there have been sharp disagreements about ...
More
A central motif of R. G. Collingwood's philosophy of history is the idea that historical understanding requires a re-enactment of past experience. However, there have been sharp disagreements about the acceptability of this idea, and even its meaning. This book aims to advance the critical discussion in three ways: by analysing the idea itself further, concentrating especially on the contrast which Collingwood drew between it and scientific understanding; by exploring the limits of its applicability to what historians ordinarily consider their proper subject-matter; and by clarifying the relationship between it and some other key Collingwoodian ideas, such as the place of imagination in historical inquiry, the sense in which history deals with the individual, the essential perspectivity of historical judgement, and the importance of narrative and periodisation in historical thinking. This book defends Collingwood against a good deal of recent criticism, while pointing to ways in which his position requires revision or development. This book draws upon a wide range of Collingwood's published writings, and makes considerable use of his unpublished manuscripts.Less
A central motif of R. G. Collingwood's philosophy of history is the idea that historical understanding requires a re-enactment of past experience. However, there have been sharp disagreements about the acceptability of this idea, and even its meaning. This book aims to advance the critical discussion in three ways: by analysing the idea itself further, concentrating especially on the contrast which Collingwood drew between it and scientific understanding; by exploring the limits of its applicability to what historians ordinarily consider their proper subject-matter; and by clarifying the relationship between it and some other key Collingwoodian ideas, such as the place of imagination in historical inquiry, the sense in which history deals with the individual, the essential perspectivity of historical judgement, and the importance of narrative and periodisation in historical thinking. This book defends Collingwood against a good deal of recent criticism, while pointing to ways in which his position requires revision or development. This book draws upon a wide range of Collingwood's published writings, and makes considerable use of his unpublished manuscripts.
Jenefer Robinson
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- February 2006
- ISBN:
- 9780199263653
- eISBN:
- 9780191603211
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199263655.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics
R. G. Collingwood defended a Romantic theory of art as the expression of emotion, which was so effectively criticized by the philosopher Alan Tormey in 1971 that Collingwood's theory was left for ...
More
R. G. Collingwood defended a Romantic theory of art as the expression of emotion, which was so effectively criticized by the philosopher Alan Tormey in 1971 that Collingwood's theory was left for dead. This chapter rehabilitates Collingwood's views, not as a theory of art in general, but as a theory of expression in the arts. Collingwood's idea that the expression of emotion in literature, painting, and so on is the articulation and elucidation of emotion is clarified by reference to the theory of emotion worked out in Part One. Expression should be thought of as a special kind of cognitive monitoring and as part of the emotion process.Less
R. G. Collingwood defended a Romantic theory of art as the expression of emotion, which was so effectively criticized by the philosopher Alan Tormey in 1971 that Collingwood's theory was left for dead. This chapter rehabilitates Collingwood's views, not as a theory of art in general, but as a theory of expression in the arts. Collingwood's idea that the expression of emotion in literature, painting, and so on is the articulation and elucidation of emotion is clarified by reference to the theory of emotion worked out in Part One. Expression should be thought of as a special kind of cognitive monitoring and as part of the emotion process.
William Bain
- Published in print:
- 2003
- Published Online:
- April 2004
- ISBN:
- 9780199260263
- eISBN:
- 9780191600975
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199260265.003.0007
- Subject:
- Political Science, International Relations and Politics
Offers some thoughts about the idea of trusteeship and its place in the history of international society. The first section, Unity, Progress, and Perfection of Humankind, puts forward the claim that ...
More
Offers some thoughts about the idea of trusteeship and its place in the history of international society. The first section, Unity, Progress, and Perfection of Humankind, puts forward the claim that trusteeship is a historic idea that is distinctive of a particular time and place, and, specifically, that it is intelligible in relation to other ideas that are especially characteristic of the Enlightenment. Thus, trusteeship discloses moral excellence, and indeed obtains powerful justification, when it contributes to the unity, progress, and perfection of the human family. The second section, A Society of States and a Family of Peoples, argues that these ideas call forth an understanding of international life that conceives international society and human society as forming a perfect identity, and which is underwritten by the duty that we should act so as to secure the good of our fellows. The third section, The Limit of Obligation, considers the limits of this duty, and concludes that in seeking the good of our fellows we must stop short of treating people paternally. This conclusion casts a pall of doubt on the legitimacy of trusteeship in contemporary international society, even when it is aimed at protecting fundamental human rights, because it proposes to treat an equal unequally—indeed, trusteeship is morally objectionable because it offends the irreducible sanctity of human personality by repudiating the essence of what it means to be human, a thinking and choosing agent.Less
Offers some thoughts about the idea of trusteeship and its place in the history of international society. The first section, Unity, Progress, and Perfection of Humankind, puts forward the claim that trusteeship is a historic idea that is distinctive of a particular time and place, and, specifically, that it is intelligible in relation to other ideas that are especially characteristic of the Enlightenment. Thus, trusteeship discloses moral excellence, and indeed obtains powerful justification, when it contributes to the unity, progress, and perfection of the human family. The second section, A Society of States and a Family of Peoples, argues that these ideas call forth an understanding of international life that conceives international society and human society as forming a perfect identity, and which is underwritten by the duty that we should act so as to secure the good of our fellows. The third section, The Limit of Obligation, considers the limits of this duty, and concludes that in seeking the good of our fellows we must stop short of treating people paternally. This conclusion casts a pall of doubt on the legitimacy of trusteeship in contemporary international society, even when it is aimed at protecting fundamental human rights, because it proposes to treat an equal unequally—indeed, trusteeship is morally objectionable because it offends the irreducible sanctity of human personality by repudiating the essence of what it means to be human, a thinking and choosing agent.
Giuseppina D’Oro
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- August 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780262015561
- eISBN:
- 9780262295796
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- The MIT Press
- DOI:
- 10.7551/mitpress/9780262015561.003.0016
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
This chapter explores the kind of nonreductivism defended by Davidson and compares it with that which predominated in mid-century. Davidson’s argument for the autonomy of the human sciences is ...
More
This chapter explores the kind of nonreductivism defended by Davidson and compares it with that which predominated in mid-century. Davidson’s argument for the autonomy of the human sciences is contrasted with the one developed by R. G. Collingwood as presented through the interpretative efforts of W. H. Dray. It is argued here that Davidson’s arguments against the anticausalist consensus that dominated the first half of the twentieth century were not conclusive and that the success of causalism in the latter half of the century is largely due to a return of heavy-duty metaphysics and an ontological backlash against the linguistic turn. Davidson, however, was able to preserve a kind of nonreductivism that is grounded in a distinction in kind between normative and descriptive sciences, rather than in a distinction in degree between sciences with greater or lower predictive power.Less
This chapter explores the kind of nonreductivism defended by Davidson and compares it with that which predominated in mid-century. Davidson’s argument for the autonomy of the human sciences is contrasted with the one developed by R. G. Collingwood as presented through the interpretative efforts of W. H. Dray. It is argued here that Davidson’s arguments against the anticausalist consensus that dominated the first half of the twentieth century were not conclusive and that the success of causalism in the latter half of the century is largely due to a return of heavy-duty metaphysics and an ontological backlash against the linguistic turn. Davidson, however, was able to preserve a kind of nonreductivism that is grounded in a distinction in kind between normative and descriptive sciences, rather than in a distinction in degree between sciences with greater or lower predictive power.
Jane Forsey
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- May 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199964369
- eISBN:
- 9780199333233
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199964369.003.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics, General
Chapter One provides an ontology of design that distinguishes it from art and craft as a specific kind of object with unique characteristics. A critical engagement with traditional formalist and ...
More
Chapter One provides an ontology of design that distinguishes it from art and craft as a specific kind of object with unique characteristics. A critical engagement with traditional formalist and expression theories of art demonstrate that design cannot be theorized in the same manner as the fine arts, or craft. Design, instead, is primarily functional, meant to be used rather than contemplated, and is distinct from art in particular because of its lack of profundity and originality, or because of its familiarity and quiddity. The properties that characterize design as unique also indicate that it is a candidate for aesthetic appraisal that merits separate attention.Less
Chapter One provides an ontology of design that distinguishes it from art and craft as a specific kind of object with unique characteristics. A critical engagement with traditional formalist and expression theories of art demonstrate that design cannot be theorized in the same manner as the fine arts, or craft. Design, instead, is primarily functional, meant to be used rather than contemplated, and is distinct from art in particular because of its lack of profundity and originality, or because of its familiarity and quiddity. The properties that characterize design as unique also indicate that it is a candidate for aesthetic appraisal that merits separate attention.
W. J. Mander
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- January 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780198748892
- eISBN:
- 9780191811548
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198748892.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, History of Philosophy
Taking up the topic of metaethics, this chapter explores one broad argument type of anti-realist character which has been popular among idealists, an argument type which holds that attributions of ...
More
Taking up the topic of metaethics, this chapter explores one broad argument type of anti-realist character which has been popular among idealists, an argument type which holds that attributions of value must always be understood by reference to some idealized act of valuation from which they would result. Three forms of this argument type are considered, anchoring the value judgement alternatively in ideal love (Plato, Brentano), in ideal desire (T. H. Green), or in ideal choice (J. S. Mackenzie, R. G. Collingwood). Focusing in particular on the version which employs the notion of idealized desire, the chapter discusses both the stages involved in extrapolating to such a limit, and the various objections which might be made against the strategy.Less
Taking up the topic of metaethics, this chapter explores one broad argument type of anti-realist character which has been popular among idealists, an argument type which holds that attributions of value must always be understood by reference to some idealized act of valuation from which they would result. Three forms of this argument type are considered, anchoring the value judgement alternatively in ideal love (Plato, Brentano), in ideal desire (T. H. Green), or in ideal choice (J. S. Mackenzie, R. G. Collingwood). Focusing in particular on the version which employs the notion of idealized desire, the chapter discusses both the stages involved in extrapolating to such a limit, and the various objections which might be made against the strategy.
Menachem Fisch
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780226514482
- eISBN:
- 9780226514659
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226514659.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Science
The chapter describes how the project of Creatively Undecided evolved out of my earlier work. The works of George Peacock, William Whewell, John Herschel and W. R. Hamilton I studied during the 1990s ...
More
The chapter describes how the project of Creatively Undecided evolved out of my earlier work. The works of George Peacock, William Whewell, John Herschel and W. R. Hamilton I studied during the 1990s ended up defying the marked Popperian and Collingwoodian perspective to which I was committed. The creative, yet painfully split hybridic accounts of science and mathematics they produced bespoke a profound normative inner struggle that challenged my philosophical commitments. Philosophical work on Popper’s identification of rationality and criticism alerted me to criticism’s inherent normative constraints, namely, that one could not criticize the norms employed in criticizing, which supposedly rendered them immune to critical reflection. The key was to realize that normative criticism from without could render one ambivalent to the norms it challenged, and hence susceptible to self-criticism. The chapter concludes with a brief description of the philosophical account of the transformative impact of such criticism presented in The View from Within of 2011, on which the present study builds.Less
The chapter describes how the project of Creatively Undecided evolved out of my earlier work. The works of George Peacock, William Whewell, John Herschel and W. R. Hamilton I studied during the 1990s ended up defying the marked Popperian and Collingwoodian perspective to which I was committed. The creative, yet painfully split hybridic accounts of science and mathematics they produced bespoke a profound normative inner struggle that challenged my philosophical commitments. Philosophical work on Popper’s identification of rationality and criticism alerted me to criticism’s inherent normative constraints, namely, that one could not criticize the norms employed in criticizing, which supposedly rendered them immune to critical reflection. The key was to realize that normative criticism from without could render one ambivalent to the norms it challenged, and hence susceptible to self-criticism. The chapter concludes with a brief description of the philosophical account of the transformative impact of such criticism presented in The View from Within of 2011, on which the present study builds.
D. W. Harding
- Published in print:
- 2019
- Published Online:
- January 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780198817734
- eISBN:
- 9780191887949
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198817734.003.0011
- Subject:
- Classical Studies, Archaeology: Non-Classical
Defining Romanization is problematical, not least because there was no uniform concept throughout the empire of what it meant to be ‘Roman’. Assessments from the early twentieth century, when the ...
More
Defining Romanization is problematical, not least because there was no uniform concept throughout the empire of what it meant to be ‘Roman’. Assessments from the early twentieth century, when the term was introduced, automatically included a value judgement that Romanization of native communities was a good thing, and something that they would have aspired to. This was based largely on the colonialist viewpoint of classical scholars of the late Victorian and Edwardian eras that presupposed that the imposition of ‘civilized’ standards on subject peoples was morally justified and practically beneficial. Changing attitudes have not only rendered this viewpoint unacceptable, but have also made debate itself unacceptable in some quarters. In reality interaction between native communities and the occupying regime was different in different parts of Britain, and the impact of occupation, in terms of urban development, for example, was extremely variable. For much of the twentieth century Romano-British archaeology was built upon the historically based legacy of Haverfield and Collingwood, in which military history formed the basic framework for research, but new approaches were triggered in the 1990s by advances in technology and development-funded archaeology. Recent research has argued that south-eastern Britain at least already included client kingdoms of Rome, though the case remains controversial.Less
Defining Romanization is problematical, not least because there was no uniform concept throughout the empire of what it meant to be ‘Roman’. Assessments from the early twentieth century, when the term was introduced, automatically included a value judgement that Romanization of native communities was a good thing, and something that they would have aspired to. This was based largely on the colonialist viewpoint of classical scholars of the late Victorian and Edwardian eras that presupposed that the imposition of ‘civilized’ standards on subject peoples was morally justified and practically beneficial. Changing attitudes have not only rendered this viewpoint unacceptable, but have also made debate itself unacceptable in some quarters. In reality interaction between native communities and the occupying regime was different in different parts of Britain, and the impact of occupation, in terms of urban development, for example, was extremely variable. For much of the twentieth century Romano-British archaeology was built upon the historically based legacy of Haverfield and Collingwood, in which military history formed the basic framework for research, but new approaches were triggered in the 1990s by advances in technology and development-funded archaeology. Recent research has argued that south-eastern Britain at least already included client kingdoms of Rome, though the case remains controversial.
Richard Moran
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- June 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780190633776
- eISBN:
- 9780190633806
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190633776.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics, Philosophy of Mind
In addition to his contributions to the history of philosophy, Bernard Williams’s later work is concerned with more explicit reflection on the role of history in the constitution of the discipline of ...
More
In addition to his contributions to the history of philosophy, Bernard Williams’s later work is concerned with more explicit reflection on the role of history in the constitution of the discipline of philosophy, the fact that, unlike the case of the natural sciences, the great figures of philosophy are part of the contemporary discussion in philosophy. In addition these reflections became increasingly concerned with what is distinctive about history as a form of knowledge, a form of knowledge which does not attract the attention of analytic philosophers. Historical knowledge is at once empirical and evidence-based but also, insofar as it concerns human affairs and institutions, obliged to make sense of and reconstruct the perspective of the practices and participants themselves. Part of the importance of historical understanding for Williams lies in its position as a model for humanistic knowledge that is non-reductionist while also being non-ideal, empirical, and “impure.”Less
In addition to his contributions to the history of philosophy, Bernard Williams’s later work is concerned with more explicit reflection on the role of history in the constitution of the discipline of philosophy, the fact that, unlike the case of the natural sciences, the great figures of philosophy are part of the contemporary discussion in philosophy. In addition these reflections became increasingly concerned with what is distinctive about history as a form of knowledge, a form of knowledge which does not attract the attention of analytic philosophers. Historical knowledge is at once empirical and evidence-based but also, insofar as it concerns human affairs and institutions, obliged to make sense of and reconstruct the perspective of the practices and participants themselves. Part of the importance of historical understanding for Williams lies in its position as a model for humanistic knowledge that is non-reductionist while also being non-ideal, empirical, and “impure.”
Alan G. Gross
- Published in print:
- 2018
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780190637774
- eISBN:
- 9780197559727
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780190637774.003.0014
- Subject:
- Education, Teaching of a Specific Subject
“This View of Life,” Stephen Jay Gould’s long-running essay series, forms a massive refutation of any charge that in popularized science truth and entertainment are incompatible. These essays ...
More
“This View of Life,” Stephen Jay Gould’s long-running essay series, forms a massive refutation of any charge that in popularized science truth and entertainment are incompatible. These essays invariably “follow two unbreakable rules,” Gould writes: “I never lie and I strive mightily not to bore you.” In the prologue to the collection Bully for Brontosaurus, Gould is more explicit concerning his first rule: “No compromises with conceptual richness; no bypassing of ambiguity or ignorance; removal of jargon, of course, but no dumbing down of ideas (any conceptual complexity can be conveyed in English).” Concerning the second rule, Gould is silent: he practices but does not reflect on his ability to shock us, to imitate in prose the last line of Muir’s “The Animals.” On the surface, a statement of biblical fact, its position at the poem’s end belies its factual status. We experience instead the shock of our existential state, burdened by history, by memory, by the apprehension of death. Muir has sprung a surprise, giv-ing us an experience Longinus long ago described, the literary sublime. By literary means as well, in his essays on science and its history, Gould can spring analogous surprises. In Gould, however, the literary sublime is always in the service of its scientific counterpart. I single out a group among his three hundred essays, each of which is so structured that we vicariously experience the process of discovery. Their twists and turns seem at first to lead nowhere; no picture emerges until, suddenly, one does, a surprise that evokes the experience of the scientific sublime. A very young Adam Smith—an Adam Smith well before The Wealth of Nations—tells us how us how surprise opens a path to this sublime: “When one accustomed object appears after another, which it does not usually follow, it first excites, by its unexpectedness, the sentiment properly called surprise, and afterwards, by the singularity of the succession, or order of its appearance, the sentiment properly called wonder.”
Less
“This View of Life,” Stephen Jay Gould’s long-running essay series, forms a massive refutation of any charge that in popularized science truth and entertainment are incompatible. These essays invariably “follow two unbreakable rules,” Gould writes: “I never lie and I strive mightily not to bore you.” In the prologue to the collection Bully for Brontosaurus, Gould is more explicit concerning his first rule: “No compromises with conceptual richness; no bypassing of ambiguity or ignorance; removal of jargon, of course, but no dumbing down of ideas (any conceptual complexity can be conveyed in English).” Concerning the second rule, Gould is silent: he practices but does not reflect on his ability to shock us, to imitate in prose the last line of Muir’s “The Animals.” On the surface, a statement of biblical fact, its position at the poem’s end belies its factual status. We experience instead the shock of our existential state, burdened by history, by memory, by the apprehension of death. Muir has sprung a surprise, giv-ing us an experience Longinus long ago described, the literary sublime. By literary means as well, in his essays on science and its history, Gould can spring analogous surprises. In Gould, however, the literary sublime is always in the service of its scientific counterpart. I single out a group among his three hundred essays, each of which is so structured that we vicariously experience the process of discovery. Their twists and turns seem at first to lead nowhere; no picture emerges until, suddenly, one does, a surprise that evokes the experience of the scientific sublime. A very young Adam Smith—an Adam Smith well before The Wealth of Nations—tells us how us how surprise opens a path to this sublime: “When one accustomed object appears after another, which it does not usually follow, it first excites, by its unexpectedness, the sentiment properly called surprise, and afterwards, by the singularity of the succession, or order of its appearance, the sentiment properly called wonder.”