H. Matthew Kramer
- Published in print:
- 2003
- Published Online:
- January 2005
- ISBN:
- 9780199247561
- eISBN:
- 9780191601927
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199247560.003.0002
- Subject:
- Political Science, Political Theory
Delineates the principal ideas that make up my theory of freedom as negative liberty. Raises a number of challenges to positive-liberty theories and to the civic-republican conception of freedom, ...
More
Delineates the principal ideas that make up my theory of freedom as negative liberty. Raises a number of challenges to positive-liberty theories and to the civic-republican conception of freedom, with sustained criticisms of the work of Quentin Skinner and Philip Pettit. It likewise objects to moralized conceptions of particular freedoms and unfreedoms. It pays particular attention to the ways in which such freedoms and unfreedoms exist over time.Less
Delineates the principal ideas that make up my theory of freedom as negative liberty. Raises a number of challenges to positive-liberty theories and to the civic-republican conception of freedom, with sustained criticisms of the work of Quentin Skinner and Philip Pettit. It likewise objects to moralized conceptions of particular freedoms and unfreedoms. It pays particular attention to the ways in which such freedoms and unfreedoms exist over time.
Ian Carter
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198294535
- eISBN:
- 9780191598951
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198294530.003.0009
- Subject:
- Political Science, Political Theory
In order to show that freedom is (at least theoretically) measurable, one must show that the different kinds of constraint on freedom (physical impossibility, threats, difficulty) can be aggregated ...
More
In order to show that freedom is (at least theoretically) measurable, one must show that the different kinds of constraint on freedom (physical impossibility, threats, difficulty) can be aggregated so as to provide overall freedom judgements. This can be done by reducing all of these kinds of constraint to the constraint of physical impossibility. This solution does not involve a “restrictivist” conception of constraints on freedom. Once it is recognized that overall freedom is a function of the physical compossibility of actions, it should also be recognized that agents for whom particular actions are difficult or costly, or who are subjected to coercion, generally suffer reductions in their degrees of overall freedom. Further analysis of the notion of constraints shows that this liberal conception of freedom is not, as is often supposed, ultimately distinguishable either from traditionally socialist conceptions or from the republican conception recently proposed by Philip Pettit.Less
In order to show that freedom is (at least theoretically) measurable, one must show that the different kinds of constraint on freedom (physical impossibility, threats, difficulty) can be aggregated so as to provide overall freedom judgements. This can be done by reducing all of these kinds of constraint to the constraint of physical impossibility. This solution does not involve a “restrictivist” conception of constraints on freedom. Once it is recognized that overall freedom is a function of the physical compossibility of actions, it should also be recognized that agents for whom particular actions are difficult or costly, or who are subjected to coercion, generally suffer reductions in their degrees of overall freedom. Further analysis of the notion of constraints shows that this liberal conception of freedom is not, as is often supposed, ultimately distinguishable either from traditionally socialist conceptions or from the republican conception recently proposed by Philip Pettit.
Ian Carter
- Published in print:
- 1999
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198294535
- eISBN:
- 9780191598951
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198294530.003.0010
- Subject:
- Political Science, Political Theory
The freedom of a group of individuals is best understood as the sum of the degrees of freedom of its individual members. G. A. Cohen has opposed this view, arguing that a group (e.g. the proletariat) ...
More
The freedom of a group of individuals is best understood as the sum of the degrees of freedom of its individual members. G. A. Cohen has opposed this view, arguing that a group (e.g. the proletariat) can suffer from “collective unfreedom”, where collective unfreedom signifies the incompossibility of given actions of different individuals, and can coexist with the individual freedom of each to perform her respective action. A closer analysis of the notion of collective unfreedom suggests that what is true in claims about collective unfreedom can be stated in terms of individual unfreedom. Cohen is nevertheless right in suggesting that degrees of group freedom can vary depending, among other things, on the structure of property rights. This contradicts Hillel Steiner’s claim that group freedom is constant-sum, a claim which arises out of a failure to distinguish between the number of actions a possible world can contain and the number of freedoms it can contain.Less
The freedom of a group of individuals is best understood as the sum of the degrees of freedom of its individual members. G. A. Cohen has opposed this view, arguing that a group (e.g. the proletariat) can suffer from “collective unfreedom”, where collective unfreedom signifies the incompossibility of given actions of different individuals, and can coexist with the individual freedom of each to perform her respective action. A closer analysis of the notion of collective unfreedom suggests that what is true in claims about collective unfreedom can be stated in terms of individual unfreedom. Cohen is nevertheless right in suggesting that degrees of group freedom can vary depending, among other things, on the structure of property rights. This contradicts Hillel Steiner’s claim that group freedom is constant-sum, a claim which arises out of a failure to distinguish between the number of actions a possible world can contain and the number of freedoms it can contain.
Anja Eleveld
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- September 2020
- ISBN:
- 9781447340010
- eISBN:
- 9781447340164
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Policy Press
- DOI:
- 10.1332/policypress/9781447340010.003.0012
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Public and Welfare
This chapter examines how the republican theory of non-domination can be used for a normative analysis of WTW relationships. It is argued that Lovett’s conception of non-domination captures some of ...
More
This chapter examines how the republican theory of non-domination can be used for a normative analysis of WTW relationships. It is argued that Lovett’s conception of non-domination captures some of the defining elements of these relationships. However, his conception of rules is (too) strongly rooted in the ideas of reasonability and impartiality, as a result of which vulnerable people in particular are at risk of being excluded from its (potentially protective) scope. Therefore, a republican normative analysis of WTW practices should also take account of Pettit’s more inclusive, democratic account of the republican theory of non-domination that is more attentive to the need for democratic oversight over discretionary spaces of welfare officers and work supervisors.Less
This chapter examines how the republican theory of non-domination can be used for a normative analysis of WTW relationships. It is argued that Lovett’s conception of non-domination captures some of the defining elements of these relationships. However, his conception of rules is (too) strongly rooted in the ideas of reasonability and impartiality, as a result of which vulnerable people in particular are at risk of being excluded from its (potentially protective) scope. Therefore, a republican normative analysis of WTW practices should also take account of Pettit’s more inclusive, democratic account of the republican theory of non-domination that is more attentive to the need for democratic oversight over discretionary spaces of welfare officers and work supervisors.
William J. Talbott
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- January 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780195173482
- eISBN:
- 9780199872176
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195173482.003.0014
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Political Philosophy
This chapter responds to a variety of objections, including the following: that the account is not really consequentialist; that it gives too much priority to states as the guarantors of human ...
More
This chapter responds to a variety of objections, including the following: that the account is not really consequentialist; that it gives too much priority to states as the guarantors of human rights; that it makes human rights too contingent; that it is implausible that there is any formula for equity; that the claim of first-person authority is implausible; that it leaves out important values, such as the badness of domination; and that it requires a division in practical reason that is “repugnant to common sense”. The chapter also explains why he depends on his readers to help detect his fudge factors and theoretical inertia.Less
This chapter responds to a variety of objections, including the following: that the account is not really consequentialist; that it gives too much priority to states as the guarantors of human rights; that it makes human rights too contingent; that it is implausible that there is any formula for equity; that the claim of first-person authority is implausible; that it leaves out important values, such as the badness of domination; and that it requires a division in practical reason that is “repugnant to common sense”. The chapter also explains why he depends on his readers to help detect his fudge factors and theoretical inertia.
Peter Lamarque
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- September 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199577460
- eISBN:
- 9780191722998
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199577460.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Aesthetics, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter defends a key thesis: Some aesthetic properties are possessed essentially by some works of art. This thesis (individual- or I-essentialism) is distinguished from other essentialist ...
More
This chapter defends a key thesis: Some aesthetic properties are possessed essentially by some works of art. This thesis (individual- or I-essentialism) is distinguished from other essentialist claims in aesthetics (e.g., class- or C-essentialism). The supposed supervenience of aesthetic properties on sets of non-aesthetic properties is challenged or shown to be trivial when the breadth of the requisite base properties (including intentional properties) is revealed. Prominent among the essential aesthetic properties are expressive or representational properties. The relational aspect of aesthetic properties is defended with reference to the work of Frank Sibley, Philip Pettit and Roger Scruton. Only works, not their constitutive material, can have essential aesthetic properties such that, in worlds where an appropriate (or normative) aesthetic response to a work is not possible, that work cannot exist.Less
This chapter defends a key thesis: Some aesthetic properties are possessed essentially by some works of art. This thesis (individual- or I-essentialism) is distinguished from other essentialist claims in aesthetics (e.g., class- or C-essentialism). The supposed supervenience of aesthetic properties on sets of non-aesthetic properties is challenged or shown to be trivial when the breadth of the requisite base properties (including intentional properties) is revealed. Prominent among the essential aesthetic properties are expressive or representational properties. The relational aspect of aesthetic properties is defended with reference to the work of Frank Sibley, Philip Pettit and Roger Scruton. Only works, not their constitutive material, can have essential aesthetic properties such that, in worlds where an appropriate (or normative) aesthetic response to a work is not possible, that work cannot exist.
Ralph Wedgwood
- Published in print:
- 2007
- Published Online:
- May 2008
- ISBN:
- 9780199251315
- eISBN:
- 9780191719127
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199251315.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This chapter considers two other rival accounts of normative statements. First, it considers the account of ‘Cornell moral realism’ which is based on applying the causal theory of reference to ...
More
This chapter considers two other rival accounts of normative statements. First, it considers the account of ‘Cornell moral realism’ which is based on applying the causal theory of reference to normative terms. Secondly, it considers the accounts of David Lewis, Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit, and Michael Smith, which are based on the attempt to give a ‘conceptual analysis’ of normative statements. It is argued that both of these approaches fail, largely because they cannot accommodate the sort of ‘internalism’ that was argued for in Chapter 1.Less
This chapter considers two other rival accounts of normative statements. First, it considers the account of ‘Cornell moral realism’ which is based on applying the causal theory of reference to normative terms. Secondly, it considers the accounts of David Lewis, Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit, and Michael Smith, which are based on the attempt to give a ‘conceptual analysis’ of normative statements. It is argued that both of these approaches fail, largely because they cannot accommodate the sort of ‘internalism’ that was argued for in Chapter 1.
José Luis Bermúdez
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- May 2009
- ISBN:
- 9780199548026
- eISBN:
- 9780191720246
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199548026.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Science
This chapter explores the relation between the different dimensions of rationality. Previous chapters have argued that decision theory cannot be developed in a way that will satisfy the requirements ...
More
This chapter explores the relation between the different dimensions of rationality. Previous chapters have argued that decision theory cannot be developed in a way that will satisfy the requirements of all three dimensions of rationality. This chapter assesses the prospects for taking decision theory to be a theory of rationality in just one of the three dimensions. It evaluates Pettit's claim that decision theory provides a normative canon of rationality, but not a deliberative calculus of rationality, as well as Kahneman and Tversky's proposal to use prospect theory as a explanatory-predictive complement to decision theory. The upshot of the chapter is that the three dimensions of rationality cannot be separated out.Less
This chapter explores the relation between the different dimensions of rationality. Previous chapters have argued that decision theory cannot be developed in a way that will satisfy the requirements of all three dimensions of rationality. This chapter assesses the prospects for taking decision theory to be a theory of rationality in just one of the three dimensions. It evaluates Pettit's claim that decision theory provides a normative canon of rationality, but not a deliberative calculus of rationality, as well as Kahneman and Tversky's proposal to use prospect theory as a explanatory-predictive complement to decision theory. The upshot of the chapter is that the three dimensions of rationality cannot be separated out.
Richard Dagger
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- May 2009
- ISBN:
- 9780199559169
- eISBN:
- 9780191720956
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199559169.003.0007
- Subject:
- Law, Philosophy of Law, Constitutional and Administrative Law
This chapter looks to the republican tradition of political thought for guidance in unravelling the problems that surround the analysis and practice of criminal law. It argues that republicanism can ...
More
This chapter looks to the republican tradition of political thought for guidance in unravelling the problems that surround the analysis and practice of criminal law. It argues that republicanism can help us to understand what ‘the public’ is, how an action may wrong it, and why some of those wrongs should be designated crimes. It shows how a republican theory of criminal law draws on elements of the three neo-republican approaches: Pettit's (and Braithwaite's) emphasis on dominion, Huigens' emphasis on virtue, and Marshall's and Duff's emphasis on crimes as ‘shared wrongs’. These help explain the public stake in preserving some sense of community or solidarity where the law is concerned.Less
This chapter looks to the republican tradition of political thought for guidance in unravelling the problems that surround the analysis and practice of criminal law. It argues that republicanism can help us to understand what ‘the public’ is, how an action may wrong it, and why some of those wrongs should be designated crimes. It shows how a republican theory of criminal law draws on elements of the three neo-republican approaches: Pettit's (and Braithwaite's) emphasis on dominion, Huigens' emphasis on virtue, and Marshall's and Duff's emphasis on crimes as ‘shared wrongs’. These help explain the public stake in preserving some sense of community or solidarity where the law is concerned.
Michael Devitt
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- February 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199280803
- eISBN:
- 9780191723254
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199280803.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, Philosophy of Science
‘Worldmaking’ is the antirealist doctrine that we make the known world with our concepts. It is Constructivism without a commitment to relativism. This chapter considers the relation between ...
More
‘Worldmaking’ is the antirealist doctrine that we make the known world with our concepts. It is Constructivism without a commitment to relativism. This chapter considers the relation between Worldmaking and the global response-dependency theory of concepts urged by Pettit. According to this theory all concepts are of dispositions to produce a certain sort of response in normal humans in normal conditions. Pettit denies that this theory leads to Worldmaking. The chapter argues that he is wrong. The theory leads to the view that all properties are response-dependent and this leads to Worldmaking. For that reason alone Pettit's theory of concepts should be rejected.Less
‘Worldmaking’ is the antirealist doctrine that we make the known world with our concepts. It is Constructivism without a commitment to relativism. This chapter considers the relation between Worldmaking and the global response-dependency theory of concepts urged by Pettit. According to this theory all concepts are of dispositions to produce a certain sort of response in normal humans in normal conditions. Pettit denies that this theory leads to Worldmaking. The chapter argues that he is wrong. The theory leads to the view that all properties are response-dependent and this leads to Worldmaking. For that reason alone Pettit's theory of concepts should be rejected.
Colin Tyler (ed.)
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- September 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199271665
- eISBN:
- 9780191709364
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199271665.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Political Philosophy
This chapter establishes that Green's republicanism overcomes the limitations of contemporary philosophical attempts to reinvigorate the republican tradition. Green avoids the contemporary dichotomy ...
More
This chapter establishes that Green's republicanism overcomes the limitations of contemporary philosophical attempts to reinvigorate the republican tradition. Green avoids the contemporary dichotomy between ‘protective’ (Pettit) and ‘civic humanist’ (Sandel, Honohan) republicanism. The chapter begins by highlighting Green's self-identification as a republican, with the second section sketching the contemporary republican landscape. Section three establishes that Green's conceptions of ‘independence’ and ‘true freedom’ are superior to those used by contemporary philosophers. Green's conceptualisations of true freedom and intersubjective recognition are also explored. Section four analyses Greenian ‘civic virtue’ and its interrelationships with freedom. Section five explores the democratic contestability of the ‘common good’ in Green's republicanism, something that causes significant difficulties for contemporary republicans. Section six critically assesses Green's decentralised political structure, before section seven explores his radical theory of patriotism and civil disobedience. The conclusion argues that Green's republicanism is more coherent, integrated, and compelling than the leading contemporary versions.Less
This chapter establishes that Green's republicanism overcomes the limitations of contemporary philosophical attempts to reinvigorate the republican tradition. Green avoids the contemporary dichotomy between ‘protective’ (Pettit) and ‘civic humanist’ (Sandel, Honohan) republicanism. The chapter begins by highlighting Green's self-identification as a republican, with the second section sketching the contemporary republican landscape. Section three establishes that Green's conceptions of ‘independence’ and ‘true freedom’ are superior to those used by contemporary philosophers. Green's conceptualisations of true freedom and intersubjective recognition are also explored. Section four analyses Greenian ‘civic virtue’ and its interrelationships with freedom. Section five explores the democratic contestability of the ‘common good’ in Green's republicanism, something that causes significant difficulties for contemporary republicans. Section six critically assesses Green's decentralised political structure, before section seven explores his radical theory of patriotism and civil disobedience. The conclusion argues that Green's republicanism is more coherent, integrated, and compelling than the leading contemporary versions.
Albert W. Dzur
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199874095
- eISBN:
- 9780199980024
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199874095.003.0002
- Subject:
- Political Science, Political Theory
Criminal justice scholars such as Bottoms and Pratt argue that citizen participation has played a decisive role in the expansionary penal state. Their “penal populism” thesis is exemplified by the ...
More
Criminal justice scholars such as Bottoms and Pratt argue that citizen participation has played a decisive role in the expansionary penal state. Their “penal populism” thesis is exemplified by the classic case of three-strikes legislation in California, which was propelled forward by distrust of officials, erosion of barriers between electoral politics and criminal justice policy, equation of effective punishment with severity, and emotive political rhetoric. As a remedy, Lacey, Pettit, Zimring, and others recommend greater professionalization and more insulation between criminal justice policymaking and the public. This chapter challenges this approach on practical and normative grounds, arguing that sealing off the criminal justice process from the public blocks education, assumption of responsibility, and trust-building experiences. Penal populism, it argues, is not a matter of too much citizen participation, but of a mass mobilization lacking constructive elements of other citizen movements. The restorative justice movement is instructive, as advocates reject the idea of the public as naturally punitive. Programs involve citizens as needed resources for humanizing mainstream criminal justice procedures, as, for example, lay volunteers in circle sentencing and family group conferencing dialogues.Less
Criminal justice scholars such as Bottoms and Pratt argue that citizen participation has played a decisive role in the expansionary penal state. Their “penal populism” thesis is exemplified by the classic case of three-strikes legislation in California, which was propelled forward by distrust of officials, erosion of barriers between electoral politics and criminal justice policy, equation of effective punishment with severity, and emotive political rhetoric. As a remedy, Lacey, Pettit, Zimring, and others recommend greater professionalization and more insulation between criminal justice policymaking and the public. This chapter challenges this approach on practical and normative grounds, arguing that sealing off the criminal justice process from the public blocks education, assumption of responsibility, and trust-building experiences. Penal populism, it argues, is not a matter of too much citizen participation, but of a mass mobilization lacking constructive elements of other citizen movements. The restorative justice movement is instructive, as advocates reject the idea of the public as naturally punitive. Programs involve citizens as needed resources for humanizing mainstream criminal justice procedures, as, for example, lay volunteers in circle sentencing and family group conferencing dialogues.
Philip Pettit
- Published in print:
- 2002
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780199251872
- eISBN:
- 9780191598227
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199251878.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
The essays selected here come in three packages. The first set of essays is concerned with the rule‐following, response‐dependent character of thought; the second, with the many factors to which ...
More
The essays selected here come in three packages. The first set of essays is concerned with the rule‐following, response‐dependent character of thought; the second, with the many factors to which choice is rationally responsive—and by reference to which choice can be explained—consistently being under the control of such reason‐giving thought; and the third, with the implications of this multiple sensitivity for how best to regulate human institutions with a view to securing a desirable normative order.Less
The essays selected here come in three packages. The first set of essays is concerned with the rule‐following, response‐dependent character of thought; the second, with the many factors to which choice is rationally responsive—and by reference to which choice can be explained—consistently being under the control of such reason‐giving thought; and the third, with the implications of this multiple sensitivity for how best to regulate human institutions with a view to securing a desirable normative order.
Frank Jackson
- Published in print:
- 2000
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780198250616
- eISBN:
- 9780191597787
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0198250614.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
This chapter gives an account of what cognitivism in ethics is and argues that the a priori global nature of the supervenience of the ethical on the descriptive requires cognitivists in ethics to ...
More
This chapter gives an account of what cognitivism in ethics is and argues that the a priori global nature of the supervenience of the ethical on the descriptive requires cognitivists in ethics to identify ethical properties with descriptive ones. It argues that we can locate ethical properties with descriptive ones in terms of the role ethical properties play in folk morality, a view of ethics I call, with Philip Pettit, ‘moral functionalism’.Less
This chapter gives an account of what cognitivism in ethics is and argues that the a priori global nature of the supervenience of the ethical on the descriptive requires cognitivists in ethics to identify ethical properties with descriptive ones. It argues that we can locate ethical properties with descriptive ones in terms of the role ethical properties play in folk morality, a view of ethics I call, with Philip Pettit, ‘moral functionalism’.
Adrienne M. Martin
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- October 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780691151526
- eISBN:
- 9781400848706
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691151526.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
This chapter presents a series of challenge cases for the orthodox definition of hope—cases that show this definition cannot distinguish strong hopes for highly unlikely outcomes from either weaker ...
More
This chapter presents a series of challenge cases for the orthodox definition of hope—cases that show this definition cannot distinguish strong hopes for highly unlikely outcomes from either weaker hopes or even despair directed at those outcomes. To truly capture what it is to “hope against hope,” we need to supplement the orthodox definition. The chapter then considers and rejects three recent proposals about how to supplement the definition. Although these three proposals—from Philip Pettit, Luc Bovens, and Ariel Meirav—are not ultimately successful, this chapter argues that there are important lessons we should take from each. In light of these lessons, the chapter proposes the incorporation analysis of hope, whereby hoping for an outcome is a distinctive way of treating one's own attitudes toward the outcome.Less
This chapter presents a series of challenge cases for the orthodox definition of hope—cases that show this definition cannot distinguish strong hopes for highly unlikely outcomes from either weaker hopes or even despair directed at those outcomes. To truly capture what it is to “hope against hope,” we need to supplement the orthodox definition. The chapter then considers and rejects three recent proposals about how to supplement the definition. Although these three proposals—from Philip Pettit, Luc Bovens, and Ariel Meirav—are not ultimately successful, this chapter argues that there are important lessons we should take from each. In light of these lessons, the chapter proposes the incorporation analysis of hope, whereby hoping for an outcome is a distinctive way of treating one's own attitudes toward the outcome.
Joshua Gert
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- January 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199657544
- eISBN:
- 9780191742217
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199657544.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter explains and defends the general method to be used throughout the book. It is inspired by the later Wittgenstein, and draws heavily on developments of the Wittgensteinian view offered by ...
More
This chapter explains and defends the general method to be used throughout the book. It is inspired by the later Wittgenstein, and draws heavily on developments of the Wittgensteinian view offered by Philip Pettit and by Huw Price. One part of the strategy is to pay adequate attention to the fact that language is a social practice; it is something we use to get things done. Another part of the strategy is to avoid appeal to theoretically substantial notions of truth or reference in providing demystifying philosophical accounts.Less
This chapter explains and defends the general method to be used throughout the book. It is inspired by the later Wittgenstein, and draws heavily on developments of the Wittgensteinian view offered by Philip Pettit and by Huw Price. One part of the strategy is to pay adequate attention to the fact that language is a social practice; it is something we use to get things done. Another part of the strategy is to avoid appeal to theoretically substantial notions of truth or reference in providing demystifying philosophical accounts.
Matthew C. Hunter
- Published in print:
- 2020
- Published Online:
- September 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780226390253
- eISBN:
- 9780226390390
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226390390.003.0005
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
This chapter considers how late-eighteenth-century chemical replicas after chemically unstable academic paintings were rediscovered in the early 1860s. Seeking to acquire a prototype of James Watt’s ...
More
This chapter considers how late-eighteenth-century chemical replicas after chemically unstable academic paintings were rediscovered in the early 1860s. Seeking to acquire a prototype of James Watt’s steam engine from the Soho manufactory established by Matthew Boulton in the mid-1760s, curator Francis Pettit Smith unearthed a set of replicas, which he called “sun pictures.” Smith identified the images as early photographs. On that basis, he claimed that photography must have been invented at Soho in the final decades of the eighteenth century. Although Smith’s story found support among several leading photographers in the 1860s, it was strongly opposed by Matthew Piers Watt Boulton, grandson of the Soho industrialist. This chapter demonstrates how M.P.W. Boulton destroyed Smith’s story. It also highlights the ways in which Boulton simultaneously integrated Smith’s chemo-mechanical findings into his own aircraft designs. The chapter concludes by arguing for the extensive connections between the leading inventors of photography and combustion-engine research.Less
This chapter considers how late-eighteenth-century chemical replicas after chemically unstable academic paintings were rediscovered in the early 1860s. Seeking to acquire a prototype of James Watt’s steam engine from the Soho manufactory established by Matthew Boulton in the mid-1760s, curator Francis Pettit Smith unearthed a set of replicas, which he called “sun pictures.” Smith identified the images as early photographs. On that basis, he claimed that photography must have been invented at Soho in the final decades of the eighteenth century. Although Smith’s story found support among several leading photographers in the 1860s, it was strongly opposed by Matthew Piers Watt Boulton, grandson of the Soho industrialist. This chapter demonstrates how M.P.W. Boulton destroyed Smith’s story. It also highlights the ways in which Boulton simultaneously integrated Smith’s chemo-mechanical findings into his own aircraft designs. The chapter concludes by arguing for the extensive connections between the leading inventors of photography and combustion-engine research.
Michael E. Bratman
- Published in print:
- 2022
- Published Online:
- May 2022
- ISBN:
- 9780197580899
- eISBN:
- 9780197580936
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780197580899.001.0001
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
Our human lives involve remarkable forms of practical organization: diachronic organization of individual activity, small-scale organization of shared action, and the organization of institutions. A ...
More
Our human lives involve remarkable forms of practical organization: diachronic organization of individual activity, small-scale organization of shared action, and the organization of institutions. A theory of human action should help us understand these multiple forms of human practical organization and their interrelations. This book argues that a key is our capacity for planning agency. Drawing on earlier work on the roles of planning agency in the cross-temporal and small-scale social organization of our agency, this book focuses on the role of our planning agency within our organized institutions. It draws on ideas, inspired by H. L. A. Hart, that our organized institutions are rule-guided, and that to understand this we need a theory of social rules. This book draws on the planning theory of shared intention and the underlying theory of plan rationality to understand social rules. It understands an organized institution as involving authority-according social rules of procedure. It provides a model of organized institutions that makes room for pluralistic divergence. This leads to a model of institutional intention and—drawing on ideas from Harry Frankfurt—institutional intentional agency. The account charts a path between views of, among others, Kirk Ludwig, Philip Pettit, and Scott Shapiro. It sees our capacity for planning agency as a core capacity that underlies not only string quartets and informal social rules but also, thereby, the rule-guided structure of organized institutions and institutional agency. And it supports adjustments in views of mind, intention, and agency that are built into Donald Davidson’s field-shaping work.Less
Our human lives involve remarkable forms of practical organization: diachronic organization of individual activity, small-scale organization of shared action, and the organization of institutions. A theory of human action should help us understand these multiple forms of human practical organization and their interrelations. This book argues that a key is our capacity for planning agency. Drawing on earlier work on the roles of planning agency in the cross-temporal and small-scale social organization of our agency, this book focuses on the role of our planning agency within our organized institutions. It draws on ideas, inspired by H. L. A. Hart, that our organized institutions are rule-guided, and that to understand this we need a theory of social rules. This book draws on the planning theory of shared intention and the underlying theory of plan rationality to understand social rules. It understands an organized institution as involving authority-according social rules of procedure. It provides a model of organized institutions that makes room for pluralistic divergence. This leads to a model of institutional intention and—drawing on ideas from Harry Frankfurt—institutional intentional agency. The account charts a path between views of, among others, Kirk Ludwig, Philip Pettit, and Scott Shapiro. It sees our capacity for planning agency as a core capacity that underlies not only string quartets and informal social rules but also, thereby, the rule-guided structure of organized institutions and institutional agency. And it supports adjustments in views of mind, intention, and agency that are built into Donald Davidson’s field-shaping work.
Robert S. Taylor
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- April 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198798736
- eISBN:
- 9780191839504
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198798736.001.0001
- Subject:
- Political Science, Political Theory
How can citizens best protect themselves from the arbitrary power of abusive spouses, tyrannical bosses, and corrupt politicians? Exit Left makes the case that in each of these three spheres the ...
More
How can citizens best protect themselves from the arbitrary power of abusive spouses, tyrannical bosses, and corrupt politicians? Exit Left makes the case that in each of these three spheres the answer is the same: exit. By promoting open and competitive markets and providing the information and financial resources necessary to enable exit, we can empower people’s voices and offer them an escape from abuse and exploitation. This will advance a conception of freedom, viz. freedom as non-domination (FND), that is central to contemporary republican thought. Neo-republicans have typically promoted FND through constitutional means (the separation of powers, judicial review, the rule of law, and federalism) and participatory ones (democratic elections and oversight), but this book focuses on economic means, ones that have been neglected by contemporary republicans but were commonly invoked in the older, commercial-republican tradition of Alexander Hamilton, Immanuel Kant, and Adam Smith. Just as Philip Pettit and other neo-republicans have revived and revised classical republicanism, so this book will do the same for commercial republicanism. This revival will enlarge republican practice by encouraging greater use of market mechanisms, even as it hews closely to existing republican theory.Less
How can citizens best protect themselves from the arbitrary power of abusive spouses, tyrannical bosses, and corrupt politicians? Exit Left makes the case that in each of these three spheres the answer is the same: exit. By promoting open and competitive markets and providing the information and financial resources necessary to enable exit, we can empower people’s voices and offer them an escape from abuse and exploitation. This will advance a conception of freedom, viz. freedom as non-domination (FND), that is central to contemporary republican thought. Neo-republicans have typically promoted FND through constitutional means (the separation of powers, judicial review, the rule of law, and federalism) and participatory ones (democratic elections and oversight), but this book focuses on economic means, ones that have been neglected by contemporary republicans but were commonly invoked in the older, commercial-republican tradition of Alexander Hamilton, Immanuel Kant, and Adam Smith. Just as Philip Pettit and other neo-republicans have revived and revised classical republicanism, so this book will do the same for commercial republicanism. This revival will enlarge republican practice by encouraging greater use of market mechanisms, even as it hews closely to existing republican theory.
Andrew von Hirsch and Andrew Ashworth
- Published in print:
- 1996
- Published Online:
- March 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780198262411
- eISBN:
- 9780191682339
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198262411.003.0012
- Subject:
- Law, Criminal Law and Criminology
Among recent critiques of the desert model is one by a sociologist and a philosopher, John Braithwaite and Phillip Pettit. They consider the whole idea of sentences apportioned to the gravity of ...
More
Among recent critiques of the desert model is one by a sociologist and a philosopher, John Braithwaite and Phillip Pettit. They consider the whole idea of sentences apportioned to the gravity of offences to be mistaken, and offer an alternative, consequentialist theory of justice that supposedly would decide sentencing policy better. Braithwaite and Pettit wish to retain the forward-looking and aggregative features of the utilitarian calculus. They are troubled, however, by the calculus's seeming disregard of the person. Their solution, essentially, is to retain the calculus but change its measure from utility to something that would give greater emphasis to persons' capacity for choice. They term this something else ‘dominion’. The argument for proportionate sanctions was made on reprobative grounds: punishments convey censure or blame, and hence should be ordered according to the degree of blameworthiness of the conduct.Less
Among recent critiques of the desert model is one by a sociologist and a philosopher, John Braithwaite and Phillip Pettit. They consider the whole idea of sentences apportioned to the gravity of offences to be mistaken, and offer an alternative, consequentialist theory of justice that supposedly would decide sentencing policy better. Braithwaite and Pettit wish to retain the forward-looking and aggregative features of the utilitarian calculus. They are troubled, however, by the calculus's seeming disregard of the person. Their solution, essentially, is to retain the calculus but change its measure from utility to something that would give greater emphasis to persons' capacity for choice. They term this something else ‘dominion’. The argument for proportionate sanctions was made on reprobative grounds: punishments convey censure or blame, and hence should be ordered according to the degree of blameworthiness of the conduct.