Peter Simons and David Bell
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199890576
- eISBN:
- 9780199980031
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199890576.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
Meinong’s theory of objects and Husserl’s formal ontology are divergent but cognate responses to Brentano’s flawed theory of intentional inexistence. While Meinong emphasized objects and their ...
More
Meinong’s theory of objects and Husserl’s formal ontology are divergent but cognate responses to Brentano’s flawed theory of intentional inexistence. While Meinong emphasized objects and their variety, Husserl emphasized contents and their variety. Their theories agree on many salient issues both of phenomenology and ontology. Meinong, like Twardowski, upheld the objectuality of all intentional acts, and was therefore constrained to seek objects for acts lacking standard objects. Husserl by contrast rejects non-existents and explains the same phenomena by saying such lack objects but are phenomenologically indistinguishable from acts that have objects. This is modified by Husserl’s later theory of noemata on the one hand and Meinong’s recognition of the semantic role of incomplete auxiliary objects on the other. As a result, their theories materially converged. This chapter charts their principal convergences and disagreements and portrays them both as independent continuers of Brentano’s messianic drive to establish a scientific philosophy.Less
Meinong’s theory of objects and Husserl’s formal ontology are divergent but cognate responses to Brentano’s flawed theory of intentional inexistence. While Meinong emphasized objects and their variety, Husserl emphasized contents and their variety. Their theories agree on many salient issues both of phenomenology and ontology. Meinong, like Twardowski, upheld the objectuality of all intentional acts, and was therefore constrained to seek objects for acts lacking standard objects. Husserl by contrast rejects non-existents and explains the same phenomena by saying such lack objects but are phenomenologically indistinguishable from acts that have objects. This is modified by Husserl’s later theory of noemata on the one hand and Meinong’s recognition of the semantic role of incomplete auxiliary objects on the other. As a result, their theories materially converged. This chapter charts their principal convergences and disagreements and portrays them both as independent continuers of Brentano’s messianic drive to establish a scientific philosophy.
David Bostock
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- September 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199651443
- eISBN:
- 9780191741197
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199651443.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
The chapter outlines Russell’s early theory of denoting in 1903, and the reasons why it should be abandoned. The new theory of 1905 contains objections to the rival views of definite descriptions due ...
More
The chapter outlines Russell’s early theory of denoting in 1903, and the reasons why it should be abandoned. The new theory of 1905 contains objections to the rival views of definite descriptions due to Meinong and to Frege, and these are endorsed. (But there is no full discussion of what Russell saw as his main argument, using the example of ‘Gray’s Elegy’.) Russell’s new theory does solve the puzzles that he mentions, at least for definite descriptions, but since the puzzles seem to apply also to names the solution is only partial at this stage. In this article Russell was concerned with our ordinary language, which leaves him open to the kind of objections raised by Strawson (1950). But in later developments he moves from language to thought, and then to a supposedly ‘perfect’ language.Less
The chapter outlines Russell’s early theory of denoting in 1903, and the reasons why it should be abandoned. The new theory of 1905 contains objections to the rival views of definite descriptions due to Meinong and to Frege, and these are endorsed. (But there is no full discussion of what Russell saw as his main argument, using the example of ‘Gray’s Elegy’.) Russell’s new theory does solve the puzzles that he mentions, at least for definite descriptions, but since the puzzles seem to apply also to names the solution is only partial at this stage. In this article Russell was concerned with our ordinary language, which leaves him open to the kind of objections raised by Strawson (1950). But in later developments he moves from language to thought, and then to a supposedly ‘perfect’ language.
Graham Priest
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- July 2005
- ISBN:
- 9780199262540
- eISBN:
- 9780191602672
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199262543.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
Chapter 5 provides a discussion of Quine and Russell on non-existent objects. Their arguments aim to show that Meinong’s notion of such objects is incoherent. Quine’s well known argument about the ...
More
Chapter 5 provides a discussion of Quine and Russell on non-existent objects. Their arguments aim to show that Meinong’s notion of such objects is incoherent. Quine’s well known argument about the fat man in the doorway is discussed and rejected.Less
Chapter 5 provides a discussion of Quine and Russell on non-existent objects. Their arguments aim to show that Meinong’s notion of such objects is incoherent. Quine’s well known argument about the fat man in the doorway is discussed and rejected.
Nathan Salmon
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- February 2006
- ISBN:
- 9780199284719
- eISBN:
- 9780191603235
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199284717.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
Quine’s dictum that to be is to be a value of a variable is rejected on the grounds that variables range over nonexistents. Many things do not exist. This observation is consistent with actualism, ...
More
Quine’s dictum that to be is to be a value of a variable is rejected on the grounds that variables range over nonexistents. Many things do not exist. This observation is consistent with actualism, the doctrine that everything there is exists. All things inevitably have properties. Existence and actuality are properties, Kant notwithstanding.Less
Quine’s dictum that to be is to be a value of a variable is rejected on the grounds that variables range over nonexistents. Many things do not exist. This observation is consistent with actualism, the doctrine that everything there is exists. All things inevitably have properties. Existence and actuality are properties, Kant notwithstanding.
A. N. Prior
- Published in print:
- 1971
- Published Online:
- October 2011
- ISBN:
- 9780198243540
- eISBN:
- 9780191680694
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198243540.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics, Philosophy of Language
From objects of thought in the sense of ‘what we think’, this chapter now turns to objects of thought in the more natural sense of what we think of or about. It discusses ‘thinking of’ as a genuine ...
More
From objects of thought in the sense of ‘what we think’, this chapter now turns to objects of thought in the more natural sense of what we think of or about. It discusses ‘thinking of’ as a genuine relation; Reid on the possible unreality and generality of objects of thought; Brentano, Meinong, and Findlay on objects of thought; and Miss Anscombe on intentional objects.Less
From objects of thought in the sense of ‘what we think’, this chapter now turns to objects of thought in the more natural sense of what we think of or about. It discusses ‘thinking of’ as a genuine relation; Reid on the possible unreality and generality of objects of thought; Brentano, Meinong, and Findlay on objects of thought; and Miss Anscombe on intentional objects.
David Lewis
- Published in print:
- 1983
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780195032048
- eISBN:
- 9780199833382
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0195032047.003.0015
- Subject:
- Philosophy, General
Drawing on his account of possible worlds, Lewis attempts to specify the truth‐conditions for statements of the form, ‘In fiction f, Φ’. According to Lewis, such truth in fiction is the product of ...
More
Drawing on his account of possible worlds, Lewis attempts to specify the truth‐conditions for statements of the form, ‘In fiction f, Φ’. According to Lewis, such truth in fiction is the product of two sources: “the explicit content of the fiction, and a background consisting either of the facts about our world or of the beliefs overt in the community of origin.” In the postscript, Lewis addresses the topics of make‐believe, impossible fictions, and fiction in the service of truth.Less
Drawing on his account of possible worlds, Lewis attempts to specify the truth‐conditions for statements of the form, ‘In fiction f, Φ’. According to Lewis, such truth in fiction is the product of two sources: “the explicit content of the fiction, and a background consisting either of the facts about our world or of the beliefs overt in the community of origin.” In the postscript, Lewis addresses the topics of make‐believe, impossible fictions, and fiction in the service of truth.
Mark Sainsbury
- Published in print:
- 2018
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780198803348
- eISBN:
- 9780191841538
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198803348.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Language
Intentionality is a property of mental states: their being directed on things, or about things. Intensionality is a semantic property, marked by such features as failure of truth preservation when ...
More
Intentionality is a property of mental states: their being directed on things, or about things. Intensionality is a semantic property, marked by such features as failure of truth preservation when one referring expression is replaced by another with the same reference. Attributions of intentional states are intensional. This first chapter sets out the basic distinctions, describes some puzzles about intensionality (for example, how it is possible to think about unicorns when there are none to think about), and sketches the path to be taken in the rest of the book.Less
Intentionality is a property of mental states: their being directed on things, or about things. Intensionality is a semantic property, marked by such features as failure of truth preservation when one referring expression is replaced by another with the same reference. Attributions of intentional states are intensional. This first chapter sets out the basic distinctions, describes some puzzles about intensionality (for example, how it is possible to think about unicorns when there are none to think about), and sketches the path to be taken in the rest of the book.
- Published in print:
- 2007
- Published Online:
- March 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780226111728
- eISBN:
- 9780226111780
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- University of Chicago Press
- DOI:
- 10.7208/chicago/9780226111780.003.0005
- Subject:
- History, History of Science, Technology, and Medicine
This chapter reports the age of scientific determinism. The most widely cited response to the education ministry came from the eminent Graz psychologist Alexius Meinong. Meinong had been a student of ...
More
This chapter reports the age of scientific determinism. The most widely cited response to the education ministry came from the eminent Graz psychologist Alexius Meinong. Meinong had been a student of Franz Brentano. Brentano was a sympathetic figure to Austria's newly powerful liberals. Franz Exner's concept of the “humanistic” value of science study reemerged at the center of a new Austrian pedagogical movement. Karl Exner addressed the ministry's “Instructions” as an authority on the Gymnasium physics curriculum. Meinong and Höfler's program for teaching students to distinguish “evident” knowledge from mere possibility was one answer to the liberals' problem of steering between dogmatism and skepticism. Adolf Exner was arguing that probabilistic science was a model of reasoning fit for training the future leaders of a liberal state. Adolf's probabilistic model of rationality evoked the liberal culture of the Sommerfrische, with its celebration of the peasant's experiential knowledge of nature.Less
This chapter reports the age of scientific determinism. The most widely cited response to the education ministry came from the eminent Graz psychologist Alexius Meinong. Meinong had been a student of Franz Brentano. Brentano was a sympathetic figure to Austria's newly powerful liberals. Franz Exner's concept of the “humanistic” value of science study reemerged at the center of a new Austrian pedagogical movement. Karl Exner addressed the ministry's “Instructions” as an authority on the Gymnasium physics curriculum. Meinong and Höfler's program for teaching students to distinguish “evident” knowledge from mere possibility was one answer to the liberals' problem of steering between dogmatism and skepticism. Adolf Exner was arguing that probabilistic science was a model of reasoning fit for training the future leaders of a liberal state. Adolf's probabilistic model of rationality evoked the liberal culture of the Sommerfrische, with its celebration of the peasant's experiential knowledge of nature.
Saul A. Kripke
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- September 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199928385
- eISBN:
- 9780199332953
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199928385.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Language
Ordinary language allows for quantification over fictional and mythical entities. We can say that Hamlet exists without commitment either to a moody Danish prince or to a shadowy Meinongian entity, ...
More
Ordinary language allows for quantification over fictional and mythical entities. We can say that Hamlet exists without commitment either to a moody Danish prince or to a shadowy Meinongian entity, dwelling in some realm between being and non-being. The fictional character Hamlet is an abstract entity, existing in virtue of the fact that Shakespeare engaged in a certain sort of pretense—in particular, writing a work containing a character with that name. Although Hamlet does exist, he does not exist in the way that a concrete entity exists. His existence is similar to the existence of a nation. Both entities exist in virtue of the activities of, or relations between, concrete individuals.Less
Ordinary language allows for quantification over fictional and mythical entities. We can say that Hamlet exists without commitment either to a moody Danish prince or to a shadowy Meinongian entity, dwelling in some realm between being and non-being. The fictional character Hamlet is an abstract entity, existing in virtue of the fact that Shakespeare engaged in a certain sort of pretense—in particular, writing a work containing a character with that name. Although Hamlet does exist, he does not exist in the way that a concrete entity exists. His existence is similar to the existence of a nation. Both entities exist in virtue of the activities of, or relations between, concrete individuals.
Mark Textor
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- September 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780199685479
- eISBN:
- 9780191765636
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780199685479.003.0004
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
Brentano endorsed (conceptual) primitivism about intentionality and the view that intentionality is fully revealed to us in its instantiations. The pros and cons of Brentano’s view that ...
More
Brentano endorsed (conceptual) primitivism about intentionality and the view that intentionality is fully revealed to us in its instantiations. The pros and cons of Brentano’s view that intentionality is a conceptually primitive property of every mental act are discussed. On the one hand, it makes clear why we need to distinguish between the immanent object (intentional correlate) and the external object. But, on the other hand, propositional attitudes turn out to be a major problem for intentionality primitivism. Meinong accepted Brentano’s Thesis as well as the existence of ‘propositional attitudes’ but one cannot defend Brentano’s Thesis by saying that propositional attitudes are directed on objectives or the like. A plausible mark of the mental needs to disentangle being a mental act (process) from having an object.Less
Brentano endorsed (conceptual) primitivism about intentionality and the view that intentionality is fully revealed to us in its instantiations. The pros and cons of Brentano’s view that intentionality is a conceptually primitive property of every mental act are discussed. On the one hand, it makes clear why we need to distinguish between the immanent object (intentional correlate) and the external object. But, on the other hand, propositional attitudes turn out to be a major problem for intentionality primitivism. Meinong accepted Brentano’s Thesis as well as the existence of ‘propositional attitudes’ but one cannot defend Brentano’s Thesis by saying that propositional attitudes are directed on objectives or the like. A plausible mark of the mental needs to disentangle being a mental act (process) from having an object.
Tim Crane
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- January 2014
- ISBN:
- 9780199682744
- eISBN:
- 9780191762970
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682744.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
The problem of non-existence arises because there are true claims about non-existent intentional objects; but what is the nature of such claims and when are such claims true? Two extreme answers are ...
More
The problem of non-existence arises because there are true claims about non-existent intentional objects; but what is the nature of such claims and when are such claims true? Two extreme answers are considered and rejected: negative free logic (which does not permit enough truths) and Meinong’s ‘noneism’ (which permits too many). A middle path is defended, which holds that non-existent intentional objects have only representation-dependent properties. These are properties in what is sometimes called the ‘pleonastic’ sense. This chapter also argues that fictional characters do not exist.Less
The problem of non-existence arises because there are true claims about non-existent intentional objects; but what is the nature of such claims and when are such claims true? Two extreme answers are considered and rejected: negative free logic (which does not permit enough truths) and Meinong’s ‘noneism’ (which permits too many). A middle path is defended, which holds that non-existent intentional objects have only representation-dependent properties. These are properties in what is sometimes called the ‘pleonastic’ sense. This chapter also argues that fictional characters do not exist.
Palle Yourgrau
- Published in print:
- 2019
- Published Online:
- July 2019
- ISBN:
- 9780190247478
- eISBN:
- 9780190247492
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780190247478.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, General
Since, as most philosophers of death agree, death implies nonexistence (the corpse is not the dead person, who is essentially a living being), it follows that the mystery of death is due in no small ...
More
Since, as most philosophers of death agree, death implies nonexistence (the corpse is not the dead person, who is essentially a living being), it follows that the mystery of death is due in no small part to the paradox of nonexistence. Failing to recognize this, philosophers of death have failed to engage with the literature on the logic of nonexistence, and thus have failed to appreciate Russell’s 1902 distinction between existence and being in relation to the ontology of death. By contrast, it is maintained here that the dead are nonexistent objects that have forfeited their existence, but not their being. More generally, one of the principal goals of this study is to draw attention to the fact that the left hand of philosophy has ignored what the right hand is doing. The mysteries of death and nonexistence, which should have been approached together, have been kept apart.Less
Since, as most philosophers of death agree, death implies nonexistence (the corpse is not the dead person, who is essentially a living being), it follows that the mystery of death is due in no small part to the paradox of nonexistence. Failing to recognize this, philosophers of death have failed to engage with the literature on the logic of nonexistence, and thus have failed to appreciate Russell’s 1902 distinction between existence and being in relation to the ontology of death. By contrast, it is maintained here that the dead are nonexistent objects that have forfeited their existence, but not their being. More generally, one of the principal goals of this study is to draw attention to the fact that the left hand of philosophy has ignored what the right hand is doing. The mysteries of death and nonexistence, which should have been approached together, have been kept apart.
Mark Sainsbury
- Published in print:
- 2018
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780198803348
- eISBN:
- 9780191841538
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198803348.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Language
‘Flashbacks’ connects themes of the book to discussions by some famous historical figures. Some of the passages quoted puzzled the author greatly when he first encountered them, but viewing them in ...
More
‘Flashbacks’ connects themes of the book to discussions by some famous historical figures. Some of the passages quoted puzzled the author greatly when he first encountered them, but viewing them in the light of display theory he finds it easier to detect the seemingly conflicting pressures driving their authors.Less
‘Flashbacks’ connects themes of the book to discussions by some famous historical figures. Some of the passages quoted puzzled the author greatly when he first encountered them, but viewing them in the light of display theory he finds it easier to detect the seemingly conflicting pressures driving their authors.
Federico Lauria
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- June 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780199370962
- eISBN:
- 9780199370986
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199370962.003.0006
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, General
How are we to understand the intentionality of desire? According to the two classical views, desire is either a positive evaluation or a disposition to act. This essay examines these conceptions of ...
More
How are we to understand the intentionality of desire? According to the two classical views, desire is either a positive evaluation or a disposition to act. This essay examines these conceptions of desire and argues for a deontic alternative, namely the view that desiring is representing a state of affairs as what ought to be. Three lines of criticism of the classical pictures of desire are provided. The first concerns desire’s direction of fit, i.e. the intuition that the world should conform to our desires. The second concerns the “death of desire” principle, i.e. the intuition that one cannot desire what one represents as actual. The last pertains to desire’s role in psychological explanations, i.e. the intuition that desires can explain motivations and be explained by evaluations. Following these criticisms, three positive arguments in favor of the deontic conception are sketched.Less
How are we to understand the intentionality of desire? According to the two classical views, desire is either a positive evaluation or a disposition to act. This essay examines these conceptions of desire and argues for a deontic alternative, namely the view that desiring is representing a state of affairs as what ought to be. Three lines of criticism of the classical pictures of desire are provided. The first concerns desire’s direction of fit, i.e. the intuition that the world should conform to our desires. The second concerns the “death of desire” principle, i.e. the intuition that one cannot desire what one represents as actual. The last pertains to desire’s role in psychological explanations, i.e. the intuition that desires can explain motivations and be explained by evaluations. Following these criticisms, three positive arguments in favor of the deontic conception are sketched.
Olivier Massin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- June 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780199370962
- eISBN:
- 9780199370986
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199370962.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, General
The thesis defended in this essay, the “guise of the ought,” is that the formal objects of desires are norms (oughts-to-be or oughts-to-do) rather than values (as the “guise of the good” thesis has ...
More
The thesis defended in this essay, the “guise of the ought,” is that the formal objects of desires are norms (oughts-to-be or oughts-to-do) rather than values (as the “guise of the good” thesis has it). It is impossible, in virtue of the nature of desire, to desire something without it being presented as something that ought to be or that one ought to do. This view is defended by pointing to a key distinction between values and norms: positive and negative norms (obligation and interdiction) are interdefinable through negation; positive and negative values aren’t. This contrast between norms and values, it is argued, is mirrored within the psychological realm by the contrast between desires and emotions. Positive and negative desires are interdefinable through negation, but positive and negative emotions aren’t. The overall, Meinongian picture suggested is that norms are to desires what values are to emotions.Less
The thesis defended in this essay, the “guise of the ought,” is that the formal objects of desires are norms (oughts-to-be or oughts-to-do) rather than values (as the “guise of the good” thesis has it). It is impossible, in virtue of the nature of desire, to desire something without it being presented as something that ought to be or that one ought to do. This view is defended by pointing to a key distinction between values and norms: positive and negative norms (obligation and interdiction) are interdefinable through negation; positive and negative values aren’t. This contrast between norms and values, it is argued, is mirrored within the psychological realm by the contrast between desires and emotions. Positive and negative desires are interdefinable through negation, but positive and negative emotions aren’t. The overall, Meinongian picture suggested is that norms are to desires what values are to emotions.
Thomas Hofweber
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- September 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780198769835
- eISBN:
- 9780191822650
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198769835.003.0003
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
This chapter argues that quantifiers in natural language are semantically underspecified. They are polysemous, with two distinct readings: a domain conditions reading and an inferential reading. On ...
More
This chapter argues that quantifiers in natural language are semantically underspecified. They are polysemous, with two distinct readings: a domain conditions reading and an inferential reading. On the inferential reading quantifier inferences are generally trivial, exploiting just the inferential role of the quantifier. However, on the domain conditions reading they are generally not trivial. Two readings of quantifiers lead to two kinds of questions about what there is. The proposal is contrasted with Carnap’s, Meinong’s, substitutional quantification, and with light vs. heavy-weight quantifiers. At the end of the chapter a solution to the first puzzle about ontology is offered and the trivial arguments for numbers, properties, and propositions are analyzed. An appendix extends the proposal to generalized quantifiers.Less
This chapter argues that quantifiers in natural language are semantically underspecified. They are polysemous, with two distinct readings: a domain conditions reading and an inferential reading. On the inferential reading quantifier inferences are generally trivial, exploiting just the inferential role of the quantifier. However, on the domain conditions reading they are generally not trivial. Two readings of quantifiers lead to two kinds of questions about what there is. The proposal is contrasted with Carnap’s, Meinong’s, substitutional quantification, and with light vs. heavy-weight quantifiers. At the end of the chapter a solution to the first puzzle about ontology is offered and the trivial arguments for numbers, properties, and propositions are analyzed. An appendix extends the proposal to generalized quantifiers.
Graham Priest
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- December 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780198783596
- eISBN:
- 9780191839856
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198783596.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
Chapter 5 provides a discussion of Quine and Russell on non-existent objects. Their arguments aim to show that Meinong’s notion of such objects is incoherent. Quine’s well known argument about the ...
More
Chapter 5 provides a discussion of Quine and Russell on non-existent objects. Their arguments aim to show that Meinong’s notion of such objects is incoherent. Quine’s well known argument about the fat man in the doorway is discussed and rejected.Less
Chapter 5 provides a discussion of Quine and Russell on non-existent objects. Their arguments aim to show that Meinong’s notion of such objects is incoherent. Quine’s well known argument about the fat man in the doorway is discussed and rejected.
Lynne Rudder Baker
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- January 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198715702
- eISBN:
- 9780191783401
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198715702.003.0015
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology, Philosophy of Religion
Peter van Inwagen recently published an essay entitled “Three Versions of the Ontological Argument” (Van Inwagen 2012). The three versions he labeled “The Meinongian Version,” “The Conceptual ...
More
Peter van Inwagen recently published an essay entitled “Three Versions of the Ontological Argument” (Van Inwagen 2012). The three versions he labeled “The Meinongian Version,” “The Conceptual Version,” and “The Modal Version,” respectively. This paper proposes a fourth version, which, for want of a better label, is called ‘The Cognitive-Ability Version’. Van Inwagen says that “Anselm’s argument presupposes, and essentially presupposes, an ontology that is … Meinongian” (Van Inwagen 2012: 8). The paper argues otherwise. If it is right, Anselm’s argument in Proslogion II is of the Cognitive-Ability variety, and not captured by any of van Inwagen’s versions of the ontological argument.Less
Peter van Inwagen recently published an essay entitled “Three Versions of the Ontological Argument” (Van Inwagen 2012). The three versions he labeled “The Meinongian Version,” “The Conceptual Version,” and “The Modal Version,” respectively. This paper proposes a fourth version, which, for want of a better label, is called ‘The Cognitive-Ability Version’. Van Inwagen says that “Anselm’s argument presupposes, and essentially presupposes, an ontology that is … Meinongian” (Van Inwagen 2012: 8). The paper argues otherwise. If it is right, Anselm’s argument in Proslogion II is of the Cognitive-Ability variety, and not captured by any of van Inwagen’s versions of the ontological argument.
Peter Simons
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- December 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198786436
- eISBN:
- 9780191828751
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198786436.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter explores a third way in construing modality—rejecting both linguistic accounts and the polycosmism of possible world theory—in the work of Alexis Meinong and Jan Łukasiewicz. Some of ...
More
This chapter explores a third way in construing modality—rejecting both linguistic accounts and the polycosmism of possible world theory—in the work of Alexis Meinong and Jan Łukasiewicz. Some of Meinong’s non-existent objects are incomplete, so in 1915 he accounts for objective probability (he says possibility) with an idea of degrees of truth: the proposition ‘My draw of a card from the pack tomorrow will be a king’ is neither simply wholly true nor wholly false, regardless of the draw I will actually make tomorrow, but has a degree of truth corresponding to the proportion of kings in a pack, between 0 and 1. Łukasiewicz, inventor of fuzzy logic, visited Meinong in Graz, and in 1913 published his own work on probability, suggesting some propositions are indefinite and have truth values between and 0 and 1; then in 1917 he began to extend this to definite propositions about future contingencies.Less
This chapter explores a third way in construing modality—rejecting both linguistic accounts and the polycosmism of possible world theory—in the work of Alexis Meinong and Jan Łukasiewicz. Some of Meinong’s non-existent objects are incomplete, so in 1915 he accounts for objective probability (he says possibility) with an idea of degrees of truth: the proposition ‘My draw of a card from the pack tomorrow will be a king’ is neither simply wholly true nor wholly false, regardless of the draw I will actually make tomorrow, but has a degree of truth corresponding to the proportion of kings in a pack, between 0 and 1. Łukasiewicz, inventor of fuzzy logic, visited Meinong in Graz, and in 1913 published his own work on probability, suggesting some propositions are indefinite and have truth values between and 0 and 1; then in 1917 he began to extend this to definite propositions about future contingencies.