Judea Pearl
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780199754649
- eISBN:
- 9780197565650
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780199754649.003.0007
- Subject:
- Clinical Medicine and Allied Health, Psychiatry
Almost two decades have passed since Paul Holland published his highly cited review paper on the Neyman-Rubin approach to causal inference (Holland, 1986). ...
More
Almost two decades have passed since Paul Holland published his highly cited review paper on the Neyman-Rubin approach to causal inference (Holland, 1986). Our understanding of causal inference has since increased severalfold, due primarily to advances in three areas: 1. Nonparametric structural equations 2. Graphical models Symbiosis between counterfactual and graphical methods 3. These advances are central to the empirical sciences because the research questions that motivate most studies in the health, social, and behavioral sciences are not statistical but causal in nature. For example, what is the efficacy of a given drug in a given population? Can data prove an employer guilty of hiring discrimination? What fraction of past crimes could have been avoided by a given policy? What was the cause of death of a given individual in a specific incident? Remarkably, although much of the conceptual framework and many of the algorithmic tools needed for tackling such problems are now well established, they are hardly known to researchers in the field who could put them into practical use. Why? Solving causal problems mathematically requires certain extensions in the standard mathematical language of statistics, and these extensions are not generally emphasized in the mainstream literature and education. As a result, large segments of the statistical research community find it hard to appreciate and benefit from the many results that causal analysis has produced in the past two decades. This chapter aims at making these advances more accessible to the general research community by, first, contrasting causal analysis with standard statistical analysis and, second, comparing and unifying various approaches to causal analysis. The aim of standard statistical analysis, typified by regression, estimation, and hypothesis-testing techniques, is to assess parameters of a distribution from samples drawn of that distribution. With the help of such parameters, one can infer associations among variables, estimate the likelihood of past and future events, as well as update the likelihood of events in light of new evidence or new measurements.
Less
Almost two decades have passed since Paul Holland published his highly cited review paper on the Neyman-Rubin approach to causal inference (Holland, 1986). Our understanding of causal inference has since increased severalfold, due primarily to advances in three areas: 1. Nonparametric structural equations 2. Graphical models Symbiosis between counterfactual and graphical methods 3. These advances are central to the empirical sciences because the research questions that motivate most studies in the health, social, and behavioral sciences are not statistical but causal in nature. For example, what is the efficacy of a given drug in a given population? Can data prove an employer guilty of hiring discrimination? What fraction of past crimes could have been avoided by a given policy? What was the cause of death of a given individual in a specific incident? Remarkably, although much of the conceptual framework and many of the algorithmic tools needed for tackling such problems are now well established, they are hardly known to researchers in the field who could put them into practical use. Why? Solving causal problems mathematically requires certain extensions in the standard mathematical language of statistics, and these extensions are not generally emphasized in the mainstream literature and education. As a result, large segments of the statistical research community find it hard to appreciate and benefit from the many results that causal analysis has produced in the past two decades. This chapter aims at making these advances more accessible to the general research community by, first, contrasting causal analysis with standard statistical analysis and, second, comparing and unifying various approaches to causal analysis. The aim of standard statistical analysis, typified by regression, estimation, and hypothesis-testing techniques, is to assess parameters of a distribution from samples drawn of that distribution. With the help of such parameters, one can infer associations among variables, estimate the likelihood of past and future events, as well as update the likelihood of events in light of new evidence or new measurements.
Patrick E. Shrout
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780199754649
- eISBN:
- 9780197565650
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780199754649.003.0005
- Subject:
- Clinical Medicine and Allied Health, Psychiatry
Both in psychopathology research and in clinical practice, causal thinking is natural and productive. In the past decades, important progress has been made ...
More
Both in psychopathology research and in clinical practice, causal thinking is natural and productive. In the past decades, important progress has been made in the treatment of disorders ranging from attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder (e.g., Connor, Glatt, Lopez, Jackson, & Melloni, 2002) to depression (e.g., Dobson, 1989; Hansen, Gartlehner, Lohr, Gaynes, & Carey, 2005) to schizophrenia (Hegarty, Baldessarini, Tohen, & Waternaux, 1994). The treatments for these disorders include pharmacological agents as well as behavioral interventions, which have been subjected to clinical trials and other empirical evaluations. Often, the treatments focus on the reduction or elimination of symptoms, but in other cases the interventions are designed to prevent the disorder itself (Brotman et al., 2008). In both instances, the interventions illustrate the best use of causal thinking to advance both scientific theory and clinical practice. When clinicians understand the causal nature of treatments, they can have confidence that their actions will lead to positive outcomes. Moreover, being able to communicate this confidence tends to increase a patient’s comfort and compliance (Becker & Maiman, 1975). Indeed, there seems to be a basic inclination for humans to engage in causal explanation, and such explanations affect both basic thinking, such as identification of categories (Rehder & Kim, 2006), and emotional functioning (Hareli & Hess, 2008). This inclination may lead some to ascribe causal explanations to mere correlations or coincidences, and many scientific texts warn researchers to be cautious about making causal claims (e.g., Maxwell & Delaney, 2004). These warnings have been taken to heart by editors, reviewers, and scientists themselves; and there is often reluctance regarding the use of causal language in the psychopathology literature. As a result, many articles simply report patterns of association and refer to mechanisms with euphemisms that imply causal thinking without addressing causal issues head-on. Over 35 years ago Rubin (1974) began to talk about strong causal inferences that could be made from experimental and nonexperimental studies using the so-called potential outcomes approach. This approach clarified the nature of the effects of causes A vs. B by asking us to consider what would happen to a given subject under these two conditions.
Less
Both in psychopathology research and in clinical practice, causal thinking is natural and productive. In the past decades, important progress has been made in the treatment of disorders ranging from attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder (e.g., Connor, Glatt, Lopez, Jackson, & Melloni, 2002) to depression (e.g., Dobson, 1989; Hansen, Gartlehner, Lohr, Gaynes, & Carey, 2005) to schizophrenia (Hegarty, Baldessarini, Tohen, & Waternaux, 1994). The treatments for these disorders include pharmacological agents as well as behavioral interventions, which have been subjected to clinical trials and other empirical evaluations. Often, the treatments focus on the reduction or elimination of symptoms, but in other cases the interventions are designed to prevent the disorder itself (Brotman et al., 2008). In both instances, the interventions illustrate the best use of causal thinking to advance both scientific theory and clinical practice. When clinicians understand the causal nature of treatments, they can have confidence that their actions will lead to positive outcomes. Moreover, being able to communicate this confidence tends to increase a patient’s comfort and compliance (Becker & Maiman, 1975). Indeed, there seems to be a basic inclination for humans to engage in causal explanation, and such explanations affect both basic thinking, such as identification of categories (Rehder & Kim, 2006), and emotional functioning (Hareli & Hess, 2008). This inclination may lead some to ascribe causal explanations to mere correlations or coincidences, and many scientific texts warn researchers to be cautious about making causal claims (e.g., Maxwell & Delaney, 2004). These warnings have been taken to heart by editors, reviewers, and scientists themselves; and there is often reluctance regarding the use of causal language in the psychopathology literature. As a result, many articles simply report patterns of association and refer to mechanisms with euphemisms that imply causal thinking without addressing causal issues head-on. Over 35 years ago Rubin (1974) began to talk about strong causal inferences that could be made from experimental and nonexperimental studies using the so-called potential outcomes approach. This approach clarified the nature of the effects of causes A vs. B by asking us to consider what would happen to a given subject under these two conditions.
E. Jane Costello and Adrian Angold
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780199754649
- eISBN:
- 9780197565650
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780199754649.003.0017
- Subject:
- Clinical Medicine and Allied Health, Psychiatry
In this chapter we (1) lay out a definition of development as it relates to psychopathology; (2) make the case that nearly all psychiatric disorders are ...
More
In this chapter we (1) lay out a definition of development as it relates to psychopathology; (2) make the case that nearly all psychiatric disorders are ‘‘developmental’’; and (3) examine, with some illustrations, methods from developmental research that can help to identify causal mechanisms leading to mental illness. The philosopher Ernst Nagel (1957, p. 15) defined development in a way that links it to both benign and pathological outcomes: . . . The concept of development involves two essential components: the notion of a system possessing a definite structure and a definite set of pre-existing capacities; and the notion of a sequential set of changes in the system, yielding relatively permanent but novel increments not only in its structure but in its modes of operation. . . . As summarized by Leon Eisenberg (1977, p. 220), "the process of development is the crucial link between genetic determinants and environmental variables, between individual psychology and sociology." It is characteristic of such systems that they consist of feedback and feedforward loops of varying complexity. Organism and environment are mutually constraining, however, with the result that developmental pathways show relatively high levels of canalization (Angoff, 1988; Cairns, Gariépy, & Hood, 1990; Gottlieb & Willoughby, 2006; Greenough, 1991; McGue, 1989; Plomin, DeFries, & Loehlin, 1977; Scarr & McCartney, 1983). Like individual ‘‘normal’’ development, diseases have inherent developmental processes of their own—processes that obey certain laws and follow certain stages even as they destroy the individual in whom they develop (Hay & Angold, 1993). A developmental approach to disease asks what happens when developmental processes embodied in pathogenesis collide with the process of ‘‘normal’’ human development. The progression seen in chronic diseases (among which we categorize most psychiatric disorders) has much in common with this view of development. It is "structured" by the nature of the transformation of the organism that begins the process, and in general, it follows a reasonably regular course, although with wide variations in rate.
Less
In this chapter we (1) lay out a definition of development as it relates to psychopathology; (2) make the case that nearly all psychiatric disorders are ‘‘developmental’’; and (3) examine, with some illustrations, methods from developmental research that can help to identify causal mechanisms leading to mental illness. The philosopher Ernst Nagel (1957, p. 15) defined development in a way that links it to both benign and pathological outcomes: . . . The concept of development involves two essential components: the notion of a system possessing a definite structure and a definite set of pre-existing capacities; and the notion of a sequential set of changes in the system, yielding relatively permanent but novel increments not only in its structure but in its modes of operation. . . . As summarized by Leon Eisenberg (1977, p. 220), "the process of development is the crucial link between genetic determinants and environmental variables, between individual psychology and sociology." It is characteristic of such systems that they consist of feedback and feedforward loops of varying complexity. Organism and environment are mutually constraining, however, with the result that developmental pathways show relatively high levels of canalization (Angoff, 1988; Cairns, Gariépy, & Hood, 1990; Gottlieb & Willoughby, 2006; Greenough, 1991; McGue, 1989; Plomin, DeFries, & Loehlin, 1977; Scarr & McCartney, 1983). Like individual ‘‘normal’’ development, diseases have inherent developmental processes of their own—processes that obey certain laws and follow certain stages even as they destroy the individual in whom they develop (Hay & Angold, 1993). A developmental approach to disease asks what happens when developmental processes embodied in pathogenesis collide with the process of ‘‘normal’’ human development. The progression seen in chronic diseases (among which we categorize most psychiatric disorders) has much in common with this view of development. It is "structured" by the nature of the transformation of the organism that begins the process, and in general, it follows a reasonably regular course, although with wide variations in rate.
Sharon Schwartz and Nicolle M. Gatto
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780199754649
- eISBN:
- 9780197565650
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780199754649.003.0006
- Subject:
- Clinical Medicine and Allied Health, Psychiatry
Epidemiology is often described as the basic science of public health. A mainstay of epidemiologic research is to uncover the causes of disease that can ...
More
Epidemiology is often described as the basic science of public health. A mainstay of epidemiologic research is to uncover the causes of disease that can serve as the basis for successful public-health interventions (e.g., Institute of Medicine, 1988; Milbank Memorial Fund Commission, 1976). A major obstacle to attaining this goal is that causes can never be seen but only inferred. For this reason, the inferences drawn from our studies must always be interpreted with caution. Considerable progress has been made in the methods required for sound causal inference. Much of this progress is rooted in a full and rich articulation of the logic behind randomized controlled trials (Holland, 1986). From this work, epidemiologists have a much better understanding of barriers to causal inference in observational studies, such as confounding and selection bias, and their tools and concepts are much more refined. The models behind this progress are often referred to as ‘‘counterfactual’’ models. Although researchers may be unfamiliar with them, they are widely (although not universally) accepted in the field. Counterfactual models underlie the methodologies that we all use. Within epidemiology, when people talk about a counterfactual model, they usually mean a potential outcomes model—also known as ‘‘Rubin’s causal model.’’ As laid out by epidemiologists, the potential outcomes model is rooted in the experimental ideas of Cox and Fisher, for which Neyman provided the first mathematical expression. It was popularized by Rubin, who extended it to observational studies, and expanded by Robins to exposures that vary over time (Maldonado & Greenland, 2002; Hernan, 2004; VanderWeele & Hernan, 2006). This rich tradition is responsible for much of the progress we have just noted. Despite this progress in methods of causal inference, a common charge in the epidemiologic literature is that public-health interventions based on the causes we identify in our studies often fail.
Less
Epidemiology is often described as the basic science of public health. A mainstay of epidemiologic research is to uncover the causes of disease that can serve as the basis for successful public-health interventions (e.g., Institute of Medicine, 1988; Milbank Memorial Fund Commission, 1976). A major obstacle to attaining this goal is that causes can never be seen but only inferred. For this reason, the inferences drawn from our studies must always be interpreted with caution. Considerable progress has been made in the methods required for sound causal inference. Much of this progress is rooted in a full and rich articulation of the logic behind randomized controlled trials (Holland, 1986). From this work, epidemiologists have a much better understanding of barriers to causal inference in observational studies, such as confounding and selection bias, and their tools and concepts are much more refined. The models behind this progress are often referred to as ‘‘counterfactual’’ models. Although researchers may be unfamiliar with them, they are widely (although not universally) accepted in the field. Counterfactual models underlie the methodologies that we all use. Within epidemiology, when people talk about a counterfactual model, they usually mean a potential outcomes model—also known as ‘‘Rubin’s causal model.’’ As laid out by epidemiologists, the potential outcomes model is rooted in the experimental ideas of Cox and Fisher, for which Neyman provided the first mathematical expression. It was popularized by Rubin, who extended it to observational studies, and expanded by Robins to exposures that vary over time (Maldonado & Greenland, 2002; Hernan, 2004; VanderWeele & Hernan, 2006). This rich tradition is responsible for much of the progress we have just noted. Despite this progress in methods of causal inference, a common charge in the epidemiologic literature is that public-health interventions based on the causes we identify in our studies often fail.