Wilfred Beckerman and Joanna Pasek
- Published in print:
- 2001
- Published Online:
- November 2003
- ISBN:
- 9780199245086
- eISBN:
- 9780191598784
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199245088.003.0004
- Subject:
- Political Science, Environmental Politics
Discusses one principle that has been suggested as a guide to the way we ought to take account of the interests of future generations, namely the principle of intergenerational ‘equity’ and its ...
More
Discusses one principle that has been suggested as a guide to the way we ought to take account of the interests of future generations, namely the principle of intergenerational ‘equity’ and its related claim of intergenerational equality, particularly in spheres such as the way we should share out ‘finite’ resources among generations. This chapter examines the possible arguments in favour of intergenerational egalitarianism and concludes that they are difficult to defend. It is proposed that egalitarianism should be replaced by the principle of ‘threshold prioritarianism’, so that our moral obligation to future generations should be based on a humanitarian concern to avoid policies that may impoverish them.Less
Discusses one principle that has been suggested as a guide to the way we ought to take account of the interests of future generations, namely the principle of intergenerational ‘equity’ and its related claim of intergenerational equality, particularly in spheres such as the way we should share out ‘finite’ resources among generations. This chapter examines the possible arguments in favour of intergenerational egalitarianism and concludes that they are difficult to defend. It is proposed that egalitarianism should be replaced by the principle of ‘threshold prioritarianism’, so that our moral obligation to future generations should be based on a humanitarian concern to avoid policies that may impoverish them.
Philip Stratton-Lake and Brad Hooker
- Published in print:
- 2006
- Published Online:
- May 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199269914
- eISBN:
- 9780191710032
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199269914.003.0008
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, General
This chapter offers a partial defence of Scanlon's buck-passing account of the relation between base properties, goodness, and practical reasons. Jonathan Dancy and Roger Crisp have both argued that ...
More
This chapter offers a partial defence of Scanlon's buck-passing account of the relation between base properties, goodness, and practical reasons. Jonathan Dancy and Roger Crisp have both argued that even if Scanlon's buck-passing account is superior to the Moorean account, there are other contending accounts that Scanlon does not consider. Against Dancy and Crisp, Stratton–Lake and Hooker argue that these proposed accounts, although genuine alternatives to the Moorean and buck-passing accounts, are nevertheless deeply problematic and do nothing to harm the case for Scanlon's account. Regarding Scanlon's two arguments, the authors find that the parsimony argument, once clarified, does offer some support for the buck-passing view, but that the appeal to value pluralism does not. Finally, they defend Scanlon's account against an ‘open question’ worry about the relation between the fact that something has reason-giving properties and its goodness.Less
This chapter offers a partial defence of Scanlon's buck-passing account of the relation between base properties, goodness, and practical reasons. Jonathan Dancy and Roger Crisp have both argued that even if Scanlon's buck-passing account is superior to the Moorean account, there are other contending accounts that Scanlon does not consider. Against Dancy and Crisp, Stratton–Lake and Hooker argue that these proposed accounts, although genuine alternatives to the Moorean and buck-passing accounts, are nevertheless deeply problematic and do nothing to harm the case for Scanlon's account. Regarding Scanlon's two arguments, the authors find that the parsimony argument, once clarified, does offer some support for the buck-passing view, but that the appeal to value pluralism does not. Finally, they defend Scanlon's account against an ‘open question’ worry about the relation between the fact that something has reason-giving properties and its goodness.
Christopher Grobe
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- September 2018
- ISBN:
- 9781479829170
- eISBN:
- 9781479839599
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- NYU Press
- DOI:
- 10.18574/nyu/9781479829170.003.0006
- Subject:
- Film, Television and Radio, Television
This essay centers around two queer British men who came to New York to perform the story of their lives in a confessional mode: Quentin Crisp in 1979 with his show An Evening with Quentin Crisp, and ...
More
This essay centers around two queer British men who came to New York to perform the story of their lives in a confessional mode: Quentin Crisp in 1979 with his show An Evening with Quentin Crisp, and Bette Bourne in 2010 with his performance A Life in Three Acts. Both shows posed as evenings of plain, immediate chat, but both, in fact, were complex, remediated things. This essay argues that such complex media schemes are, in fact, a crucial characteristic of confessional monologue, which has pervaded American theater since the 1980s.Less
This essay centers around two queer British men who came to New York to perform the story of their lives in a confessional mode: Quentin Crisp in 1979 with his show An Evening with Quentin Crisp, and Bette Bourne in 2010 with his performance A Life in Three Acts. Both shows posed as evenings of plain, immediate chat, but both, in fact, were complex, remediated things. This essay argues that such complex media schemes are, in fact, a crucial characteristic of confessional monologue, which has pervaded American theater since the 1980s.
Angus Ritchie
- Published in print:
- 2012
- Published Online:
- January 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199652518
- eISBN:
- 9780191745850
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199652518.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, Philosophy of Religion
This chapter defends our pre-philosophical commitment to moral objectivism. It is an essential prelude to the main argument, for it establishes the standard which the rest of the book will use to ...
More
This chapter defends our pre-philosophical commitment to moral objectivism. It is an essential prelude to the main argument, for it establishes the standard which the rest of the book will use to determine which secular accounts are ‘sufficiently’ objective. The chapter defends two distinct claims. The first is that in their practical deliberation, all human beings seek to approximate a truth which goes beyond their sentiments or the conventions of their culture. The second is that this quest is not in vain: which is to say, that humans have some capacity to attune their beliefs more closely to that moral truth, when they honestly and carefully seek it out. It draws on arguments made by David Enoch, Ronald Dworkin and Roger Crisp, and considers the case against moral realism presented by John Mackie.Less
This chapter defends our pre-philosophical commitment to moral objectivism. It is an essential prelude to the main argument, for it establishes the standard which the rest of the book will use to determine which secular accounts are ‘sufficiently’ objective. The chapter defends two distinct claims. The first is that in their practical deliberation, all human beings seek to approximate a truth which goes beyond their sentiments or the conventions of their culture. The second is that this quest is not in vain: which is to say, that humans have some capacity to attune their beliefs more closely to that moral truth, when they honestly and carefully seek it out. It draws on arguments made by David Enoch, Ronald Dworkin and Roger Crisp, and considers the case against moral realism presented by John Mackie.
Jonathan Dancy
- Published in print:
- 2004
- Published Online:
- January 2005
- ISBN:
- 9780199270026
- eISBN:
- 9780191601729
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/0199270023.003.0007
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
Argues against views alternative to particularism in detail, including the views of McNaughton and Rawling, Crisp, Raz, Scanlon, Hooker, Parfit, and also appeals to Aristotelian philosophy of science.
Argues against views alternative to particularism in detail, including the views of McNaughton and Rawling, Crisp, Raz, Scanlon, Hooker, Parfit, and also appeals to Aristotelian philosophy of science.
Michael J. McClymond and Gerald R. McDermott
- Published in print:
- 2011
- Published Online:
- May 2012
- ISBN:
- 9780199791606
- eISBN:
- 9780199932290
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199791606.003.0040
- Subject:
- Religion, Theology
This chapter explores some of the intellectual trajectories of Edwards both in the United States and abroad. Although Edwards never produced a distinct philosophical school of thought, continuity can ...
More
This chapter explores some of the intellectual trajectories of Edwards both in the United States and abroad. Although Edwards never produced a distinct philosophical school of thought, continuity can nevertheless be identified. On the American scene, common themes can be found in William Ellery Channing (unitarianism), Ralph Waldo Emerson (transcendentalism), Josiah Royce and William James (Harvard school, pragmatism), and even John Dewey (instrumentalism). More recently, the same can be said for William Harder Squires (German-trained American), Stephen H. Daniel (American), Miklos Vetö (Hungarian-French), and Oliver Crisp (British). As such, it is clear that Edwards's thought continues to be of interest to philosophers and has evoked complex, divergent, and even antithetical interpretations and responses.Less
This chapter explores some of the intellectual trajectories of Edwards both in the United States and abroad. Although Edwards never produced a distinct philosophical school of thought, continuity can nevertheless be identified. On the American scene, common themes can be found in William Ellery Channing (unitarianism), Ralph Waldo Emerson (transcendentalism), Josiah Royce and William James (Harvard school, pragmatism), and even John Dewey (instrumentalism). More recently, the same can be said for William Harder Squires (German-trained American), Stephen H. Daniel (American), Miklos Vetö (Hungarian-French), and Oliver Crisp (British). As such, it is clear that Edwards's thought continues to be of interest to philosophers and has evoked complex, divergent, and even antithetical interpretations and responses.
Lorne t. Kirby (ed.)
- Published in print:
- 1993
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780716770015
- eISBN:
- 9780197561225
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780716770015.003.0007
- Subject:
- Chemistry, Computational Chemistry
The proper handling of specimens for direct storage or DNA extraction and characterization is one of the most important aspects of the profiling procedure. Because DNA ...
More
The proper handling of specimens for direct storage or DNA extraction and characterization is one of the most important aspects of the profiling procedure. Because DNA typing is not yet a routine test, some laboratories may perform only the isolation portion of the overall analysis and leave the other methodologies to specialized centers. Profiling may never be required for many forensic specimens and only intermediate storage needed. It is essential that smaller centers have at least the facilities to isolate, characterize, and store DNA. A broad range of DNA sources exists. Fresh tissue usually includes whole blood, buccal epithelial cells, and hair follicles. Under special circumstances, in the medical setting, the genotyping of amniotic fluid cells, chorionic villus samples, and tissue culture fibroblasts may be required. Dried specimens usually include blood and semen stains, tooth pulp, and bone marrow. Animal trophy heads and pelts are also sources of dried DNA. Preserved or unpreserved human autopsy specimens, and tissues from animal gut piles and frozen meat, are other possible sources of DNA. As with any biological test, the quality of the results can be no better than the quality of the input sample. If the DNA is highly degraded or contaminated, it may be unusable; thus, every effort should be taken to collect, record, transport, store, and isolate materials using meticulous techniques. The specimen of choice is 1 ml or more of fresh whole EDTA blood. Anticoagulants other than EDTA may be acceptable; however, there are reports that heparin interferes with the activity of certain restriction enzymes. The quantity of DNA isolated from 1 ml of blood is usually sufficient for the necessary testing and a considerably smaller sample will often suffice. There are occasions, however, when the DNA yield is low and a repeat specimen is required; for this reason it is prudent to collect an additional sample if possible. Buccal epithelial cells obtained from mouth swabs, and hair follicles are two other general sources of fresh DNA; however, the DNA may require amplification by the polymerase chain reaction to provide sufficient material for analysis.
Less
The proper handling of specimens for direct storage or DNA extraction and characterization is one of the most important aspects of the profiling procedure. Because DNA typing is not yet a routine test, some laboratories may perform only the isolation portion of the overall analysis and leave the other methodologies to specialized centers. Profiling may never be required for many forensic specimens and only intermediate storage needed. It is essential that smaller centers have at least the facilities to isolate, characterize, and store DNA. A broad range of DNA sources exists. Fresh tissue usually includes whole blood, buccal epithelial cells, and hair follicles. Under special circumstances, in the medical setting, the genotyping of amniotic fluid cells, chorionic villus samples, and tissue culture fibroblasts may be required. Dried specimens usually include blood and semen stains, tooth pulp, and bone marrow. Animal trophy heads and pelts are also sources of dried DNA. Preserved or unpreserved human autopsy specimens, and tissues from animal gut piles and frozen meat, are other possible sources of DNA. As with any biological test, the quality of the results can be no better than the quality of the input sample. If the DNA is highly degraded or contaminated, it may be unusable; thus, every effort should be taken to collect, record, transport, store, and isolate materials using meticulous techniques. The specimen of choice is 1 ml or more of fresh whole EDTA blood. Anticoagulants other than EDTA may be acceptable; however, there are reports that heparin interferes with the activity of certain restriction enzymes. The quantity of DNA isolated from 1 ml of blood is usually sufficient for the necessary testing and a considerably smaller sample will often suffice. There are occasions, however, when the DNA yield is low and a repeat specimen is required; for this reason it is prudent to collect an additional sample if possible. Buccal epithelial cells obtained from mouth swabs, and hair follicles are two other general sources of fresh DNA; however, the DNA may require amplification by the polymerase chain reaction to provide sufficient material for analysis.
Bart Schultz
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691154770
- eISBN:
- 9781400884957
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691154770.003.0005
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Political Philosophy
This chapter examines Henry Sidgwick's utilitarianism. It first considers Sidgwick's agnosticism before discussing his views on subjects ranging from hedonism and colonialism to poverty, common-sense ...
More
This chapter examines Henry Sidgwick's utilitarianism. It first considers Sidgwick's agnosticism before discussing his views on subjects ranging from hedonism and colonialism to poverty, common-sense morality, and politics and political economy. It then looks at some of Sidgwick's writings, such as The Development of European Polity, The Elements of Politics, Lectures on the Philosophy of Kant, and The Methods of Ethics. It also explores the current reconstructions and appropriations of many of Sidgwick's positions in the works of philosophers like Roger Crisp, Rob Shaver, Peter Singer, Derek Parft, and Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek, and argues that they have contributed to a true renaissance of hedonistic and rational intuition-based utilitarianism (or at least rationalistic consequentialism) that few saw coming even in the late twentieth century.Less
This chapter examines Henry Sidgwick's utilitarianism. It first considers Sidgwick's agnosticism before discussing his views on subjects ranging from hedonism and colonialism to poverty, common-sense morality, and politics and political economy. It then looks at some of Sidgwick's writings, such as The Development of European Polity, The Elements of Politics, Lectures on the Philosophy of Kant, and The Methods of Ethics. It also explores the current reconstructions and appropriations of many of Sidgwick's positions in the works of philosophers like Roger Crisp, Rob Shaver, Peter Singer, Derek Parft, and Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek, and argues that they have contributed to a true renaissance of hedonistic and rational intuition-based utilitarianism (or at least rationalistic consequentialism) that few saw coming even in the late twentieth century.
Mark Textor
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- September 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780199685479
- eISBN:
- 9780191765636
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780199685479.003.0010
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
Brentano sees a very close relation between enjoyment and perceptual consciousness. Enjoying an activity is, Brentano proposed, an intuitive model of awareness of an activity. The chapter outlines ...
More
Brentano sees a very close relation between enjoyment and perceptual consciousness. Enjoying an activity is, Brentano proposed, an intuitive model of awareness of an activity. The chapter outlines the Aristotelian background of Brentano’s view of enjoyment, highlighting four suggestions Aristotle made about pleasure. I will assess Brentano’s arguments for the view that the proper objects of enjoyment are only activities (Hedonic Energism), and defend this view against the claims of the Hedonic Objectivists and Subjectivists. In order to understand Brentano’s development of Hedonic Energism, as well as the range of alternatives, we need to take into account that ‘enjoy’ is a polysemous word. Since there is a basic sense of ‘enjoy’ in which we can truly say that we enjoy activities, I conclude that Hedonic Energism is defensible.Less
Brentano sees a very close relation between enjoyment and perceptual consciousness. Enjoying an activity is, Brentano proposed, an intuitive model of awareness of an activity. The chapter outlines the Aristotelian background of Brentano’s view of enjoyment, highlighting four suggestions Aristotle made about pleasure. I will assess Brentano’s arguments for the view that the proper objects of enjoyment are only activities (Hedonic Energism), and defend this view against the claims of the Hedonic Objectivists and Subjectivists. In order to understand Brentano’s development of Hedonic Energism, as well as the range of alternatives, we need to take into account that ‘enjoy’ is a polysemous word. Since there is a basic sense of ‘enjoy’ in which we can truly say that we enjoy activities, I conclude that Hedonic Energism is defensible.
Glyn Davis
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- September 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780719099564
- eISBN:
- 9781526109767
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Manchester University Press
- DOI:
- 10.7228/manchester/9780719099564.003.0008
- Subject:
- Film, Television and Radio, Film
In 1992, Quentin Crisp appeared on cinema screens as Elizabeth I in Sally Potter’s Orlando; the following year, he provided the “Alternative Queen’s Message” on Channel 4 television on Christmas Day, ...
More
In 1992, Quentin Crisp appeared on cinema screens as Elizabeth I in Sally Potter’s Orlando; the following year, he provided the “Alternative Queen’s Message” on Channel 4 television on Christmas Day, going head-to-head with Elizabeth II. This chapter will revisit this cultural moment, examining the significance of Crisp’s perfonnances of “queenliness”. The late 1980s/early 1990s heralded a shift away from the lesbian and gay politics of the 1970s and “80s towards a more confrontational queer activism. Orlando can be seen as an example of early queer cinema, given its play with gender and sexuality, and Potter’s casting of Tilda Swinton (a regular collaborator of Derek Jannan). Other queer films of the time also unsettle and complicate particular moments in history, and equally employ a pointedly artificial mise-en-scene (Jannan’s Edward II, Julien’s Looking for Langston, Kalin’s Swoon). How does Crisp’s appearance–as an embodiment of the flaming, camp homosexual–complicate the film’s politics of sexuality? Does it articulate a political “clearing of the ground”, with an older gay culture (Elizabeth) giving way to a fresh queer one (Orlando)? This chapter will consider the film as a provocative transition between particular forms of cultural production–bound up with changing attitudes towards the monarchy itself.Less
In 1992, Quentin Crisp appeared on cinema screens as Elizabeth I in Sally Potter’s Orlando; the following year, he provided the “Alternative Queen’s Message” on Channel 4 television on Christmas Day, going head-to-head with Elizabeth II. This chapter will revisit this cultural moment, examining the significance of Crisp’s perfonnances of “queenliness”. The late 1980s/early 1990s heralded a shift away from the lesbian and gay politics of the 1970s and “80s towards a more confrontational queer activism. Orlando can be seen as an example of early queer cinema, given its play with gender and sexuality, and Potter’s casting of Tilda Swinton (a regular collaborator of Derek Jannan). Other queer films of the time also unsettle and complicate particular moments in history, and equally employ a pointedly artificial mise-en-scene (Jannan’s Edward II, Julien’s Looking for Langston, Kalin’s Swoon). How does Crisp’s appearance–as an embodiment of the flaming, camp homosexual–complicate the film’s politics of sexuality? Does it articulate a political “clearing of the ground”, with an older gay culture (Elizabeth) giving way to a fresh queer one (Orlando)? This chapter will consider the film as a provocative transition between particular forms of cultural production–bound up with changing attitudes towards the monarchy itself.
J. R. Nethercote
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- August 2016
- ISBN:
- 9780198753254
- eISBN:
- 9780191814853
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198753254.003.0006
- Subject:
- Economics and Finance, Economic History, Public and Welfare
The chapter deals with the apparent impossibility of an informed discussion and appreciation of federalism in Australia, despite the fact that federalism is pervasive in the ordinary working of ...
More
The chapter deals with the apparent impossibility of an informed discussion and appreciation of federalism in Australia, despite the fact that federalism is pervasive in the ordinary working of Australian life. It argues that this is because the intellectual fabric of the country in all its strands is deaf to the federal character of Australia’s character. Additionally, the force of bureaucratic mind set in Australia’s governance distorts genuine federalism—the coexistence of sovereign powers in one territory—into a bureaucratic administration tree; where a ‘head office’ enforces uniformity over ‘regional branches’. These contentions are explored by drawing on works of Crisp, Greenwood, and Weber.Less
The chapter deals with the apparent impossibility of an informed discussion and appreciation of federalism in Australia, despite the fact that federalism is pervasive in the ordinary working of Australian life. It argues that this is because the intellectual fabric of the country in all its strands is deaf to the federal character of Australia’s character. Additionally, the force of bureaucratic mind set in Australia’s governance distorts genuine federalism—the coexistence of sovereign powers in one territory—into a bureaucratic administration tree; where a ‘head office’ enforces uniformity over ‘regional branches’. These contentions are explored by drawing on works of Crisp, Greenwood, and Weber.
George Sher
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- August 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780190660413
- eISBN:
- 9780190660444
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780190660413.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy
When a person must choose among actions that will affect both him and other people, he generally takes the others’ interests to have some rational weight, but not as much as his own. This familiar ...
More
When a person must choose among actions that will affect both him and other people, he generally takes the others’ interests to have some rational weight, but not as much as his own. This familiar view is intermediate between two others: first, that only the individual’s own interests give him reason to act, and, second, that everyone else’s interests count just as much as his own. Of these two polar views, each has had forceful proponents and each can be traced to a compelling starting point. By contrast, the intermediate view that actually informs most practice seems much harder to defend. The question in this paper is whether that view is simply an unprincipled compromise between two powerful but irreconcilable intellectual pressures or whether, instead, there is some positive reason to accept itLess
When a person must choose among actions that will affect both him and other people, he generally takes the others’ interests to have some rational weight, but not as much as his own. This familiar view is intermediate between two others: first, that only the individual’s own interests give him reason to act, and, second, that everyone else’s interests count just as much as his own. Of these two polar views, each has had forceful proponents and each can be traced to a compelling starting point. By contrast, the intermediate view that actually informs most practice seems much harder to defend. The question in this paper is whether that view is simply an unprincipled compromise between two powerful but irreconcilable intellectual pressures or whether, instead, there is some positive reason to accept it
Bradford Cokelet
- Published in print:
- 2015
- Published Online:
- November 2015
- ISBN:
- 9780190204600
- eISBN:
- 9780190204624
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190204600.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Moral Philosophy, General
Chapter 10 focuses on virtue ethics, specifically the central virtue ethical thesis that the ethical quality of an agent’s actions is a function of her dispositional character. Skeptics of this view ...
More
Chapter 10 focuses on virtue ethics, specifically the central virtue ethical thesis that the ethical quality of an agent’s actions is a function of her dispositional character. Skeptics of this view quite often distinguish between an agent’s particular intentions or occurrent motives and dispositional facts about her character, contending that if we are attentive to this distinction, we will see that the virtue ethical thesis is false. While acknowledging the legitimacy of this distinction, chapter 10 presents a new interpretation and defense of the virtue ethical thesis and thus attempts to rebuff the skeptical attacks advanced by Thomas Hurka, Julia Markovits, and Roger Crisp. The key is for virtue ethicists to adopt a personal values conception of character instead of a reliable trait conception.Less
Chapter 10 focuses on virtue ethics, specifically the central virtue ethical thesis that the ethical quality of an agent’s actions is a function of her dispositional character. Skeptics of this view quite often distinguish between an agent’s particular intentions or occurrent motives and dispositional facts about her character, contending that if we are attentive to this distinction, we will see that the virtue ethical thesis is false. While acknowledging the legitimacy of this distinction, chapter 10 presents a new interpretation and defense of the virtue ethical thesis and thus attempts to rebuff the skeptical attacks advanced by Thomas Hurka, Julia Markovits, and Roger Crisp. The key is for virtue ethicists to adopt a personal values conception of character instead of a reliable trait conception.
Richard Rowland
- Published in print:
- 2019
- Published Online:
- April 2019
- ISBN:
- 9780198833611
- eISBN:
- 9780191872044
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198833611.003.0009
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
A final type of objection to the buck-passing account of value (BPA) argues that it encounters problems with evaluative properties beyond goodness simpliciter and final value. Roger Crisp and Pekka ...
More
A final type of objection to the buck-passing account of value (BPA) argues that it encounters problems with evaluative properties beyond goodness simpliciter and final value. Roger Crisp and Pekka Väyrynen have argued that BPA must extend to provide an account of certain thick concepts, namely thick evaluative concepts, but provides an implausible account of the thick evaluative. This chapter argues that if BPA must extend to the thick evaluative, it provides a plausible account of the thick evaluative. W. D. Ross argued that to have certain pro-attitudes towards an object, such as to be in a state of admiration towards something, is partially to think of the object of these pro-attitudes as good. So accounts of goodness like BPA are circular. However, this chapter argues that BPA can accommodate Ross’s view of pro-attitudes without circularity and that alternatives to BPA cannot provide a more informative account of what it is to have a pro-attitude than BPA.Less
A final type of objection to the buck-passing account of value (BPA) argues that it encounters problems with evaluative properties beyond goodness simpliciter and final value. Roger Crisp and Pekka Väyrynen have argued that BPA must extend to provide an account of certain thick concepts, namely thick evaluative concepts, but provides an implausible account of the thick evaluative. This chapter argues that if BPA must extend to the thick evaluative, it provides a plausible account of the thick evaluative. W. D. Ross argued that to have certain pro-attitudes towards an object, such as to be in a state of admiration towards something, is partially to think of the object of these pro-attitudes as good. So accounts of goodness like BPA are circular. However, this chapter argues that BPA can accommodate Ross’s view of pro-attitudes without circularity and that alternatives to BPA cannot provide a more informative account of what it is to have a pro-attitude than BPA.