John L. Bell
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- September 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780198568520
- eISBN:
- 9780191717581
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198568520.001.0001
- Subject:
- Mathematics, Logic / Computer Science / Mathematical Philosophy
This is the third edition of a well-known graduate textbook on Boolean-valued models of set theory. The aim of the first and second editions was to provide a systematic and adequately motivated ...
More
This is the third edition of a well-known graduate textbook on Boolean-valued models of set theory. The aim of the first and second editions was to provide a systematic and adequately motivated exposition of the theory of Boolean-valued models as developed by Scott and Solovay in the 1960s, deriving along the way the central set theoretic independence proofs of Cohen and others in the particularly elegant form that the Boolean-valued approach enables them to assume. In this edition, the background material has been augmented to include an introduction to Heyting algebras. It includes chapters on Boolean-valued analysis and Heyting-algebra-valued models of intuitionistic set theory.Less
This is the third edition of a well-known graduate textbook on Boolean-valued models of set theory. The aim of the first and second editions was to provide a systematic and adequately motivated exposition of the theory of Boolean-valued models as developed by Scott and Solovay in the 1960s, deriving along the way the central set theoretic independence proofs of Cohen and others in the particularly elegant form that the Boolean-valued approach enables them to assume. In this edition, the background material has been augmented to include an introduction to Heyting algebras. It includes chapters on Boolean-valued analysis and Heyting-algebra-valued models of intuitionistic set theory.
John L. Bell
- Published in print:
- 2005
- Published Online:
- September 2007
- ISBN:
- 9780198568520
- eISBN:
- 9780191717581
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198568520.003.0001
- Subject:
- Mathematics, Logic / Computer Science / Mathematical Philosophy
This chapter provides a brief account of the theory of Boolean and Heyting algebras, including the basic representation theorems and their connections with logic.
This chapter provides a brief account of the theory of Boolean and Heyting algebras, including the basic representation theorems and their connections with logic.
Hartry Field
- Published in print:
- 2008
- Published Online:
- May 2008
- ISBN:
- 9780199230747
- eISBN:
- 9780191710933
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199230747.003.0011
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
This chapter examines the simplest supervaluationist fixed points, and the ‘internal’ fixed-point theories based on them. These are not gap theories; they are ‘weakly classical’ theories in that they ...
More
This chapter examines the simplest supervaluationist fixed points, and the ‘internal’ fixed-point theories based on them. These are not gap theories; they are ‘weakly classical’ theories in that they preserve the implications of classical logic but not certain meta-rules. Most dramatically, they do not allow for reasoning by cases. Two notions of validity are distinguished (strong and weak), and the framework of deMorgan semantics and Boolean semantics is introduced and discussed.Less
This chapter examines the simplest supervaluationist fixed points, and the ‘internal’ fixed-point theories based on them. These are not gap theories; they are ‘weakly classical’ theories in that they preserve the implications of classical logic but not certain meta-rules. Most dramatically, they do not allow for reasoning by cases. Two notions of validity are distinguished (strong and weak), and the framework of deMorgan semantics and Boolean semantics is introduced and discussed.
Tim Button and Sean Walsh
- Published in print:
- 2018
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780198790396
- eISBN:
- 9780191863424
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198790396.003.0013
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics
Chapters 6-12 are driven by questions about the ability to pin down mathematical entities and to articulate mathematical concepts. This chapter is driven by similar questions about the ability to pin ...
More
Chapters 6-12 are driven by questions about the ability to pin down mathematical entities and to articulate mathematical concepts. This chapter is driven by similar questions about the ability to pin down the semantic frameworks of language. It transpires that there are not just non-standard models, but non-standard ways of doing model theory itself. In more detail: whilst we normally outline a two-valued semantics which makes sentences True or False in a model, the inference rules for first-order logic are compatible with a four-valued semantics; or a semantics with countably many values; or what-have-you. The appropriate level of generality here is that of a Boolean-valued model, which we introduce. And the plurality of possible semantic values gives rise to perhaps the ‘deepest’ level of indeterminacy questions: How can humans pin down the semantic framework for their languages? We consider three different ways for inferentialists to respond to this question.Less
Chapters 6-12 are driven by questions about the ability to pin down mathematical entities and to articulate mathematical concepts. This chapter is driven by similar questions about the ability to pin down the semantic frameworks of language. It transpires that there are not just non-standard models, but non-standard ways of doing model theory itself. In more detail: whilst we normally outline a two-valued semantics which makes sentences True or False in a model, the inference rules for first-order logic are compatible with a four-valued semantics; or a semantics with countably many values; or what-have-you. The appropriate level of generality here is that of a Boolean-valued model, which we introduce. And the plurality of possible semantic values gives rise to perhaps the ‘deepest’ level of indeterminacy questions: How can humans pin down the semantic framework for their languages? We consider three different ways for inferentialists to respond to this question.
Pieter A. M. Seuren
- Published in print:
- 2009
- Published Online:
- February 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199559480
- eISBN:
- 9780191721144
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199559480.003.0002
- Subject:
- Linguistics, Semantics and Pragmatics, Psycholinguistics / Neurolinguistics / Cognitive Linguistics
Entailment, contrariety, and contradiction stand in a triangular relation. Given negation of the predicate and given the duality of all and some, two isomorphic triangles arise, together forming an ...
More
Entailment, contrariety, and contradiction stand in a triangular relation. Given negation of the predicate and given the duality of all and some, two isomorphic triangles arise, together forming an improved notation for the traditional Square of Opposition. Logical operators are treated as (abstract) predicates, definable in terms of satisfaction conditions and shaping the logic in which they take part. Carnapian meaning postulates are discussed. Boolean algebra and corresponding standard set theory are shown to underlie standard propositional and predicate logic. The method of valuation‐space modelling is introduced as a means of providing succinct and complete representations of logical systems in such a way that their properties are open to immediate inspection. A survey is given of Russellian and generalized quantification, of internal negation, and De Morgan's laws.Less
Entailment, contrariety, and contradiction stand in a triangular relation. Given negation of the predicate and given the duality of all and some, two isomorphic triangles arise, together forming an improved notation for the traditional Square of Opposition. Logical operators are treated as (abstract) predicates, definable in terms of satisfaction conditions and shaping the logic in which they take part. Carnapian meaning postulates are discussed. Boolean algebra and corresponding standard set theory are shown to underlie standard propositional and predicate logic. The method of valuation‐space modelling is introduced as a means of providing succinct and complete representations of logical systems in such a way that their properties are open to immediate inspection. A survey is given of Russellian and generalized quantification, of internal negation, and De Morgan's laws.
A. J. Cotnoir and Achille C. Varzi
- Published in print:
- 2021
- Published Online:
- September 2021
- ISBN:
- 9780198749004
- eISBN:
- 9780191811647
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780198749004.003.0002
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind
The aim of this chapter is to provide a comprehensive introduction to classical mereology. It examines this theory by providing a clear and perspicuousaxiom system that isolates several important ...
More
The aim of this chapter is to provide a comprehensive introduction to classical mereology. It examines this theory by providing a clear and perspicuousaxiom system that isolates several important elements of any mereological theory. The chapter examines, algebraic, and set-theoretic models of classical mereology, sketching proofs of their equivalence. The new axiom system facilitates algebraic comparisons, showing that models of these axioms are complete Boolean algebras without a bottom element. Then set-theoretic models are presented, and are shown to satisfy the axioms. The chapter explains the important relationship between models and powersets, and the role of Stone’s Representation Theorem in this connection. Finally, a number of significant rival axiom systems using different mereological primitives are introduced.Less
The aim of this chapter is to provide a comprehensive introduction to classical mereology. It examines this theory by providing a clear and perspicuousaxiom system that isolates several important elements of any mereological theory. The chapter examines, algebraic, and set-theoretic models of classical mereology, sketching proofs of their equivalence. The new axiom system facilitates algebraic comparisons, showing that models of these axioms are complete Boolean algebras without a bottom element. Then set-theoretic models are presented, and are shown to satisfy the axioms. The chapter explains the important relationship between models and powersets, and the role of Stone’s Representation Theorem in this connection. Finally, a number of significant rival axiom systems using different mereological primitives are introduced.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0004
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
This chapter discusses how Boole cast logic into algebraic form. Boole was interested in symbolic analysis years before he wrote his Laws of Thought. In fact, others before him—in particular, the ...
More
This chapter discusses how Boole cast logic into algebraic form. Boole was interested in symbolic analysis years before he wrote his Laws of Thought. In fact, others before him—in particular, the German mathematician Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716)—had pursued a similar goal of reducing logic to algebra, but it was Boole who finally succeeded. What Boole described in his books is not exactly what modern users call Boolean algebra, but nevertheless it is from Boole that the modern presentation springs. The chapter first describes the essence of what Boole did using the language of sets. It then discusses Boole's algebra of sets, examples of Boolean analysis, and visualizing Boolean functions.Less
This chapter discusses how Boole cast logic into algebraic form. Boole was interested in symbolic analysis years before he wrote his Laws of Thought. In fact, others before him—in particular, the German mathematician Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716)—had pursued a similar goal of reducing logic to algebra, but it was Boole who finally succeeded. What Boole described in his books is not exactly what modern users call Boolean algebra, but nevertheless it is from Boole that the modern presentation springs. The chapter first describes the essence of what Boole did using the language of sets. It then discusses Boole's algebra of sets, examples of Boolean analysis, and visualizing Boolean functions.
Kurt Smith
- Published in print:
- 2010
- Published Online:
- September 2010
- ISBN:
- 9780199583652
- eISBN:
- 9780191723155
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199583652.003.0010
- Subject:
- Philosophy, History of Philosophy, Metaphysics/Epistemology
This chapter studies the mathematical concept of a group, early ancestors of the concept found in the works of Descartes and Leibniz. Here, it is shown exactly how the four conditions expressed by a ...
More
This chapter studies the mathematical concept of a group, early ancestors of the concept found in the works of Descartes and Leibniz. Here, it is shown exactly how the four conditions expressed by a group underwrite all of mathematics, in particular the operations of arithmetic.Less
This chapter studies the mathematical concept of a group, early ancestors of the concept found in the works of Descartes and Leibniz. Here, it is shown exactly how the four conditions expressed by a group underwrite all of mathematics, in particular the operations of arithmetic.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0002
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
This introductory chapter considers the work of mathematician George Boole (1815–1864), whose book An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (1854) would have a huge impact on humanity. Boole's ...
More
This introductory chapter considers the work of mathematician George Boole (1815–1864), whose book An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (1854) would have a huge impact on humanity. Boole's mathematics, the basis for what is now called Boolean algebra, is the subject of this book. It is also called mathematical logic, and today it is a routine analytical tool of the logic-design engineers who create the electronic circuitry that we now cannot live without, from computers to automobiles to home appliances. Boolean algebra is not traditional or classical Aristotelian logic, a subject generally taught in college by the philosophy department. Boolean algebra, by contrast, is generally in the hands of electrical engineering professors and/or the mathematics faculty.Less
This introductory chapter considers the work of mathematician George Boole (1815–1864), whose book An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (1854) would have a huge impact on humanity. Boole's mathematics, the basis for what is now called Boolean algebra, is the subject of this book. It is also called mathematical logic, and today it is a routine analytical tool of the logic-design engineers who create the electronic circuitry that we now cannot live without, from computers to automobiles to home appliances. Boolean algebra is not traditional or classical Aristotelian logic, a subject generally taught in college by the philosophy department. Boolean algebra, by contrast, is generally in the hands of electrical engineering professors and/or the mathematics faculty.
Alex Oliver and Timothy Smiley
- Published in print:
- 2013
- Published Online:
- September 2013
- ISBN:
- 9780199570423
- eISBN:
- 9780191755866
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199570423.003.0012
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics, Philosophy of Language
Plural formal logic comes in two phases. This chapter develops mid-plural logic, got by adding three logical items to the singular base of the previous chapter: plural variables, a predicate ...
More
Plural formal logic comes in two phases. This chapter develops mid-plural logic, got by adding three logical items to the singular base of the previous chapter: plural variables, a predicate expressing inclusion, and an operator symbolizing exhaustive description. Like singular logic, mid-plural logic is axiomatizable, but the price of axiomatizability is that plural variables can only occur free. As to non-logical vocabulary, the system accommodates plural constants, and predicates and function signs which take plural as well as singular arguments. It is given an appropriately topic neutral semantics. Mid-plural logic’s expressive power is illustrated by highlighting a fragment of the system—the algebra of plurals—which does for logic what Boolean algebra does for sets. The appendix to the chapter proves the metatheorems listed in the text, and proves the soundness and completeness of the axioms presented for mid-plural logic.Less
Plural formal logic comes in two phases. This chapter develops mid-plural logic, got by adding three logical items to the singular base of the previous chapter: plural variables, a predicate expressing inclusion, and an operator symbolizing exhaustive description. Like singular logic, mid-plural logic is axiomatizable, but the price of axiomatizability is that plural variables can only occur free. As to non-logical vocabulary, the system accommodates plural constants, and predicates and function signs which take plural as well as singular arguments. It is given an appropriately topic neutral semantics. Mid-plural logic’s expressive power is illustrated by highlighting a fragment of the system—the algebra of plurals—which does for logic what Boolean algebra does for sets. The appendix to the chapter proves the metatheorems listed in the text, and proves the soundness and completeness of the axioms presented for mid-plural logic.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- book
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.001.0001
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
Boolean algebra, also called Boolean logic, is at the heart of the electronic circuitry in everything we use—from our computers and cars, to home appliances. How did a system of mathematics ...
More
Boolean algebra, also called Boolean logic, is at the heart of the electronic circuitry in everything we use—from our computers and cars, to home appliances. How did a system of mathematics established in the Victorian era become the basis for such incredible technological achievements a century later? This book combines engaging problems and a colorful historical narrative to tell the remarkable story of how two men in different eras—mathematician and philosopher George Boole and electrical engineer and pioneering information theorist Claude Shannon—advanced Boolean logic and became founding fathers of the electronic communications age. The book takes readers from fundamental concepts to a deeper and more sophisticated understanding of modern digital machines, in order to explore computing and its possible limitations in the twenty-first century and beyond.Less
Boolean algebra, also called Boolean logic, is at the heart of the electronic circuitry in everything we use—from our computers and cars, to home appliances. How did a system of mathematics established in the Victorian era become the basis for such incredible technological achievements a century later? This book combines engaging problems and a colorful historical narrative to tell the remarkable story of how two men in different eras—mathematician and philosopher George Boole and electrical engineer and pioneering information theorist Claude Shannon—advanced Boolean logic and became founding fathers of the electronic communications age. The book takes readers from fundamental concepts to a deeper and more sophisticated understanding of modern digital machines, in order to explore computing and its possible limitations in the twenty-first century and beyond.
Alex Oliver and Timothy Smiley
- Published in print:
- 2016
- Published Online:
- February 2017
- ISBN:
- 9780198744382
- eISBN:
- 9780191843877
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198744382.003.0012
- Subject:
- Philosophy, Logic/Philosophy of Mathematics, Philosophy of Language
Plural formal logic comes in two phases. This chapter develops mid-plural logic, got by adding three logical items to the singular base of the previous chapter: plural variables, a predicate ...
More
Plural formal logic comes in two phases. This chapter develops mid-plural logic, got by adding three logical items to the singular base of the previous chapter: plural variables, a predicate expressing inclusion, and an operator symbolizing exhaustive description. Like singular logic, mid-plural logic is axiomatizable, but the price of axiomatizability is that plural variables can only occur free. As to non-logical vocabulary, the system accommodates plural constants, and predicates and function signs which take plural as well as singular arguments. It is given an appropriately topic neutral semantics. Mid-plural logic's expressive power is illustrated by highlighting a fragment of the system—the algebra of plurals—which does for logic what Boolean algebra is supposed to do for sets. The appendix to the chapter proves the metatheorems listed in the text, and proves the soundness and completeness of the axioms presented for mid-plural logic.Less
Plural formal logic comes in two phases. This chapter develops mid-plural logic, got by adding three logical items to the singular base of the previous chapter: plural variables, a predicate expressing inclusion, and an operator symbolizing exhaustive description. Like singular logic, mid-plural logic is axiomatizable, but the price of axiomatizability is that plural variables can only occur free. As to non-logical vocabulary, the system accommodates plural constants, and predicates and function signs which take plural as well as singular arguments. It is given an appropriately topic neutral semantics. Mid-plural logic's expressive power is illustrated by highlighting a fragment of the system—the algebra of plurals—which does for logic what Boolean algebra is supposed to do for sets. The appendix to the chapter proves the metatheorems listed in the text, and proves the soundness and completeness of the axioms presented for mid-plural logic.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0005
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
Today's digital circuitry is built with electronic technology that the telephone engineers of the 1930s and the pioneer computer designers of the 1940s would have thought to be magic. The first real ...
More
Today's digital circuitry is built with electronic technology that the telephone engineers of the 1930s and the pioneer computer designers of the 1940s would have thought to be magic. The first real digital technology took the form of electromagnetic relays in telephone switching exchanges. Then came vacuum tube digital circuitry, discrete transistors, integrated transistor circuits, and so on. But the one thing that remains the same is the math, the Boolean algebra that is the central star of this book. This chapter describes the technology that Shannon himself used in his switching analyses. It covers Switches and the logical connectives, a classic switching design problem, electromagnetic relay, the ideal diode and the relay logical AND and OR, and the bi-stable relay latch.Less
Today's digital circuitry is built with electronic technology that the telephone engineers of the 1930s and the pioneer computer designers of the 1940s would have thought to be magic. The first real digital technology took the form of electromagnetic relays in telephone switching exchanges. Then came vacuum tube digital circuitry, discrete transistors, integrated transistor circuits, and so on. But the one thing that remains the same is the math, the Boolean algebra that is the central star of this book. This chapter describes the technology that Shannon himself used in his switching analyses. It covers Switches and the logical connectives, a classic switching design problem, electromagnetic relay, the ideal diode and the relay logical AND and OR, and the bi-stable relay latch.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0003
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
This chapter presents brief biographical sketches of George Boole and Claude Shannon. George was born in Lincoln, a town in the north of England, on November 2, 1815. His father John, while simple ...
More
This chapter presents brief biographical sketches of George Boole and Claude Shannon. George was born in Lincoln, a town in the north of England, on November 2, 1815. His father John, while simple tradesman (a cobbler), taught George geometry and trigonometry, subjects John had found of great aid in his optical studies. Boole was essentially self-taught, with a formal education that stopped at what today would be a junior in high school. Eventually he became a master mathematician (who succeeded in merging algebra with logic), one held in the highest esteem by talented, highly educated men who had graduated from Cambridge and Oxford. Claude was born on April 30, 1916, in Petoskey, Michigan. He enrolled at the University of Michigan, from which he graduated in 1936 with double bachelor's degrees in mathematics and electrical engineering. It was in a class there that he was introduced to Boole's algebra of logic.Less
This chapter presents brief biographical sketches of George Boole and Claude Shannon. George was born in Lincoln, a town in the north of England, on November 2, 1815. His father John, while simple tradesman (a cobbler), taught George geometry and trigonometry, subjects John had found of great aid in his optical studies. Boole was essentially self-taught, with a formal education that stopped at what today would be a junior in high school. Eventually he became a master mathematician (who succeeded in merging algebra with logic), one held in the highest esteem by talented, highly educated men who had graduated from Cambridge and Oxford. Claude was born on April 30, 1916, in Petoskey, Michigan. He enrolled at the University of Michigan, from which he graduated in 1936 with double bachelor's degrees in mathematics and electrical engineering. It was in a class there that he was introduced to Boole's algebra of logic.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0001
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
This chapter details the background knowledge needed to read this book. Specifically, it assumes some knowledge of mathematics and electrical physics and an appreciation for the value of analytical ...
More
This chapter details the background knowledge needed to read this book. Specifically, it assumes some knowledge of mathematics and electrical physics and an appreciation for the value of analytical reasoning—but no more than a technically minded college-prep high school junior or senior would have. In particular, the math level is that of algebra, including knowing how matrices multiply. The electrical background is simple: knowing (1) that electricity comes in two polarities (positive and negative) and that electrical charges of like polarity repel and of opposite polarity attract; and (2) understanding Ohm's law for resistors (that the voltage drop across a resistor in volts is the current through the resistor in amperes times the resistance in ohms) and the circuit laws of Kirchhoff (that the sum of the voltage drops around any closed loop is zero, which is an expression of the conservation of energy; the sum of all the currents into any node is zero).Less
This chapter details the background knowledge needed to read this book. Specifically, it assumes some knowledge of mathematics and electrical physics and an appreciation for the value of analytical reasoning—but no more than a technically minded college-prep high school junior or senior would have. In particular, the math level is that of algebra, including knowing how matrices multiply. The electrical background is simple: knowing (1) that electricity comes in two polarities (positive and negative) and that electrical charges of like polarity repel and of opposite polarity attract; and (2) understanding Ohm's law for resistors (that the voltage drop across a resistor in volts is the current through the resistor in amperes times the resistance in ohms) and the circuit laws of Kirchhoff (that the sum of the voltage drops around any closed loop is zero, which is an expression of the conservation of energy; the sum of all the currents into any node is zero).
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0010
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
Boole and Shannon never studied the physics of computation. Obviously Boole simply could not have, as none of the required physics was even known in his day, and Shannon was nearing the end of his ...
More
Boole and Shannon never studied the physics of computation. Obviously Boole simply could not have, as none of the required physics was even known in his day, and Shannon was nearing the end of his career when such considerations were just beginning. And yet, both Boole's algebra and Shannon's information concepts to make many of our calculations. This chapter touches on how fundamental physics—the uncertainty principle from quantum mechanics, and thermodynamics, for example—constrain what is possible, in principle, for the computers of the far future. It argues that while there are indeed finite limitations, present-day technology falls so far short of those limits that there will be good employment for computer technologists for a very long time to come.Less
Boole and Shannon never studied the physics of computation. Obviously Boole simply could not have, as none of the required physics was even known in his day, and Shannon was nearing the end of his career when such considerations were just beginning. And yet, both Boole's algebra and Shannon's information concepts to make many of our calculations. This chapter touches on how fundamental physics—the uncertainty principle from quantum mechanics, and thermodynamics, for example—constrain what is possible, in principle, for the computers of the far future. It argues that while there are indeed finite limitations, present-day technology falls so far short of those limits that there will be good employment for computer technologists for a very long time to come.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0011
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
This chapter present the author's vision of the sort of logical problem that may soon be one that even a quantum computer would find a struggle to deal with—the decipherment of entangled legalese, ...
More
This chapter present the author's vision of the sort of logical problem that may soon be one that even a quantum computer would find a struggle to deal with—the decipherment of entangled legalese, the sort of monstrous gobbledegook one finds, for example, in the increasingly convoluted IRS tax code. In the form of a short story, that vision is “The Language Clarifier,” which first appeared in the May 1979 issue of Omni Magazine. The original title was “The Anti-Amphibological Machine,” but Omni's fiction editor thought that a tad too mystifying for readers and “suggested” the change.Less
This chapter present the author's vision of the sort of logical problem that may soon be one that even a quantum computer would find a struggle to deal with—the decipherment of entangled legalese, the sort of monstrous gobbledegook one finds, for example, in the increasingly convoluted IRS tax code. In the form of a short story, that vision is “The Language Clarifier,” which first appeared in the May 1979 issue of Omni Magazine. The original title was “The Anti-Amphibological Machine,” but Omni's fiction editor thought that a tad too mystifying for readers and “suggested” the change.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0006
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
George Boole and Claude Shannon shared a deep interest in the mathematics of probability. Boole's interest was, of course, not related to the theory of computation—he was a century too early for ...
More
George Boole and Claude Shannon shared a deep interest in the mathematics of probability. Boole's interest was, of course, not related to the theory of computation—he was a century too early for that—while Shannon's mathematical theory of communication and information processing is replete with probabilistic analyses. There is, nevertheless, an important intersection between what the two men did, which is shown in this chapter. The aim is to provide a flavor of how they reasoned and of the sort of probabilistic problem that caught their attention. Once we have finished with Boole's problem, the reader will see that it uses mathematics that will play a crucial role in answering Shannon's concern about “crummy” relays.Less
George Boole and Claude Shannon shared a deep interest in the mathematics of probability. Boole's interest was, of course, not related to the theory of computation—he was a century too early for that—while Shannon's mathematical theory of communication and information processing is replete with probabilistic analyses. There is, nevertheless, an important intersection between what the two men did, which is shown in this chapter. The aim is to provide a flavor of how they reasoned and of the sort of probabilistic problem that caught their attention. Once we have finished with Boole's problem, the reader will see that it uses mathematics that will play a crucial role in answering Shannon's concern about “crummy” relays.
H. A. F. Chaves
- Published in print:
- 1994
- Published Online:
- November 2020
- ISBN:
- 9780195085938
- eISBN:
- 9780197560525
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Oxford University Press
- DOI:
- 10.1093/oso/9780195085938.003.0013
- Subject:
- Computer Science, Software Engineering
Characteristic analysis is well known in mineral resources appraisal and has proved useful for petroleum exploration. It also can be used to integrate geological data in sedimentary basin analysis ...
More
Characteristic analysis is well known in mineral resources appraisal and has proved useful for petroleum exploration. It also can be used to integrate geological data in sedimentary basin analysis and hydrocarbon assessment, considering geological relationships and uncertainties that result from lack of basic geological knowledge, A generalization of characteristic analysis, using fuzzy—set theory and fuzzy logic, may prove better for quantification of geologic analogues and also for description of reservoir and sedimentary facies. Characteristic analysis is a discrete multivariate procedure for combining and interpreting data; Botbol (1971) originally proposed its application to geology, geochemistry, and geophysics. It has been applied mainly in the search for poorly exposed or concealed mineral deposits by exploring joint occurrences or absences of mineralogical, lithological, and structural attributes (McCammon et al., 1981). It forms part of a systematic approach to resource appraisal and integration of generalized and specific geological knowledge (Chaves, 1988, 1989; Chaves and Lewis, 1989). The technique usually requires some form of discrete sampling to be applicable—generally a spatial discretization of maps into cells or regular grids (Melo, 1988). Characteristic analysis attempts to determine the joint occurrences of various attributes that are favorable for, related to, or indicative of the occurrence of the desired phenomenon or target. In geological applications, the target usually is an economic accumulation of energy or mineral resources. Applying characteristic analysis requires the following steps: 1) the studied area is sampled using a regular square or rectangular grid of cells; 2) in each cell the favorabilities of the variables are expressed in binary or ternary form; 3) a model is chosen that indicates the cells that include the target (Sinding—Larsen et al, 1979); and 4) a combined favorability map of the area is produced that points out possible new targets. The favorability of individual variables is expressed either in binary form— assigning a value of +1 to favorable and a value of 0 to unfavorable or unevaluated variables—or in ternary form if the two states represented by 0 are distinguishable—the value +1 again means favorable, the value—1 means unfavorable, and the value 0 means unevaluated.
Less
Characteristic analysis is well known in mineral resources appraisal and has proved useful for petroleum exploration. It also can be used to integrate geological data in sedimentary basin analysis and hydrocarbon assessment, considering geological relationships and uncertainties that result from lack of basic geological knowledge, A generalization of characteristic analysis, using fuzzy—set theory and fuzzy logic, may prove better for quantification of geologic analogues and also for description of reservoir and sedimentary facies. Characteristic analysis is a discrete multivariate procedure for combining and interpreting data; Botbol (1971) originally proposed its application to geology, geochemistry, and geophysics. It has been applied mainly in the search for poorly exposed or concealed mineral deposits by exploring joint occurrences or absences of mineralogical, lithological, and structural attributes (McCammon et al., 1981). It forms part of a systematic approach to resource appraisal and integration of generalized and specific geological knowledge (Chaves, 1988, 1989; Chaves and Lewis, 1989). The technique usually requires some form of discrete sampling to be applicable—generally a spatial discretization of maps into cells or regular grids (Melo, 1988). Characteristic analysis attempts to determine the joint occurrences of various attributes that are favorable for, related to, or indicative of the occurrence of the desired phenomenon or target. In geological applications, the target usually is an economic accumulation of energy or mineral resources. Applying characteristic analysis requires the following steps: 1) the studied area is sampled using a regular square or rectangular grid of cells; 2) in each cell the favorabilities of the variables are expressed in binary or ternary form; 3) a model is chosen that indicates the cells that include the target (Sinding—Larsen et al, 1979); and 4) a combined favorability map of the area is produced that points out possible new targets. The favorability of individual variables is expressed either in binary form— assigning a value of +1 to favorable and a value of 0 to unfavorable or unevaluated variables—or in ternary form if the two states represented by 0 are distinguishable—the value +1 again means favorable, the value—1 means unfavorable, and the value 0 means unevaluated.
Paul J. Nahin
- Published in print:
- 2017
- Published Online:
- May 2018
- ISBN:
- 9780691176000
- eISBN:
- 9781400844654
- Item type:
- chapter
- Publisher:
- Princeton University Press
- DOI:
- 10.23943/princeton/9780691176000.003.0009
- Subject:
- Mathematics, History of Mathematics
This chapter discusses Turing machines. A Turing machine is the combination of a sequential, finite-state machine plus an external read/write memory storage medium called the tape (think of a ribbon ...
More
This chapter discusses Turing machines. A Turing machine is the combination of a sequential, finite-state machine plus an external read/write memory storage medium called the tape (think of a ribbon of magnetic tape). The tape is a linear sequence of squares, with each square holding one of several possible symbols. The Turing machine's power to compute comes from its tape, for two reasons. First, Turing was the first to conceive of the idea of a stored program that could be changed by the operation of the machine itself. The program, and its input data, exist together on the tape as sequences of symbols. Second, because of the arbitrarily long length of the tape, a Turing machine has the ability to “remember” what has happened in the arbitrarily distant past.Less
This chapter discusses Turing machines. A Turing machine is the combination of a sequential, finite-state machine plus an external read/write memory storage medium called the tape (think of a ribbon of magnetic tape). The tape is a linear sequence of squares, with each square holding one of several possible symbols. The Turing machine's power to compute comes from its tape, for two reasons. First, Turing was the first to conceive of the idea of a stored program that could be changed by the operation of the machine itself. The program, and its input data, exist together on the tape as sequences of symbols. Second, because of the arbitrarily long length of the tape, a Turing machine has the ability to “remember” what has happened in the arbitrarily distant past.